G. E. Moore (1873-1958) would
have hated to be called George Edward, both of which names he, for some
reason, intensely disliked. To indulge this little weakness, I shall refer to
him from now on only as Moore.
In the thin forest of
post-Nietzschean philosophers Moore stands out as a large, albeit relatively
little-known, tree. He was by no means a system-builder, and none of his theoretical
elaborations are convincing. But the rich originality of his brainstorms, the
questions he was in the habit of posing all his life, even if his answers seldom
measured up to his questions, propel him to the forefront of philosophy,
reassuring his indisputable historical greatness.
The reader may not remember, but
it was Moore who occupies a prominent place in my Contradiction entry Keynesian
Ethics As A Watchdog Over Economics, otherwise devoted to Moore’s admirer
Keynes, to which I am gladly referring my reader now, feeling no need to
reiterate in different words or to repeat verbatim the Moore passages there.
I shall however place a fairly
large stock of reference material in this entry, to serve me as a starting
point in its future rewriting and personal elaboration. So, here it is.
Moore
asserts that most other philosophers working in ethics had made the mistake he
calls the Naturalistic fallacy. The business of ethics, he agrees, is to
discover the qualities that make things good. So, for example hedonists claim
that the quality “being pleasant” is what makes things good; other
theorists could claim that “complexity” is what makes things good.
With this project Moore has no quarrel. What he objects to is the idea that, in
telling us the qualities that make things good, ethical theorists have thereby
given us an analysis of the term good and the property goodness.
Moore regards this as a serious confusion. To take an example, a hedonist might
be right to claim that something is good just in the case that it is pleasant.
But this does not mean that we can define value in terms of pleasure. Telling
what qualities make things valuable is one thing, but analyzing value is quite
another.
Moore is
well-known for the so-called open question argument, which is contained
in his greatly influential Principia Ethica. This work is one of the
main inspirations of the movement against ethical naturalism, and it is partly
responsible for the twentieth-century concern with meta-ethics.
Moore’s
argument for the indefinability of “good” (and thus for the
fallaciousness of the naturalistic fallacy) is often called the Open
Question Argument. It hinges on the nature of statements such as “Anything
that is pleasant is also good” and the possibility of asking questions such
as “Is it good that x is pleasant?” These questions are “open,”
according to Moore, and these statements are “significant”, and they will remain
so no matter what is substituted for “pleasure.” He concludes from this that
any analysis of value is bound to fail. In other words, if value could be
analyzed, then such questions and statements would be trivial and obvious.
Since they are anything but trivial and obvious, value must be indefinable.
Moore
argues that goodness cannot be analyzed in terms of any other property. He
writes:
“It may
be true that all things which are good are also something else, just as it is
true that all things which are yellow produce a certain kind of vibration in
the light. And it is a fact, that Ethics aims at discovering what are those
other properties belonging to all things which are good. But far too many
philosophers have thought that when they named those other properties they were
actually defining good; that these properties, in fact, were simply not
“other,” but absolutely and entirely the same with goodness. Therefore, we
cannot define good by explaining it in other words, we can only point to
an action or a thing and say: That is good! Similarly we cannot describe
to a blind man what yellow is whereas we can only show a sighted man a
piece of yellow paper or a yellow scrap of cloth and say: That is yellow!”
In
addition to categorizing “good” as indefinable, Moore emphasized that it
is a non-natural property. That is, two objects that are identical cannot have
different values. There cannot be two yellow shirts identical in every way (the
same shade of yellow, made at the same factory, the same brand name, the same
style, etc.), except for their reception of the predication of “good.”
(One cannot be good, and the other not good). An object’s
property of “good” is determined by what other properties the object
has. This is a property that is a product of having other properties.
Therefore, if two objects are qualitatively identical, they must have the same
value of “good.” (This is actually wrong,
as two identical substances can have opposite effect in two different sets of
circumstances, for as they say, one man’s cure is another man’s poison. Thus
the very same thing can be “good” or “bad,” depending on the
method and purpose of its use and application.)
Moore
says that once arguments based on the naturalistic fallacy have been discarded,
questions of intrinsic goodness can only be settled by appealing to what he
called moral intuitions that is self-evident propositions which recommend
themselves to moral reflection, but are not susceptible to either direct proof
or disproof. “In order to express the fact that
ethical propositions of my first class (propositions about what is good
as an end in itself) are incapable of proof or disproof I have sometimes
followed Sidgwick’s usage in calling them ‘Intuitions.’ But I beg that
it may be noticed that I am not an ‘Intuitionist,’ in the ordinary sense
of the term. Sidgwick himself seems never to have been clearly aware of the
immense importance of the difference that distinguishes his Intuitionism from
the common doctrine, which has generally been called by that name. The
Intuitionist proper is distinguished by maintaining that propositions of my second
class propositions (which assert that a certain action is right, or
a duty) are incapable of proof or disproof by enquiring into the
results of such actions. I, on the contrary, am anxious to maintain that
propositions of this kind are not “Intuitions,” whereas
propositions of my first class are Intuitions.” (Principia
Ethica, Preface.)
One of
the most important parts of Moore’s philosophical development was his break
from the idealism that dominated British philosophy (as represented in the
works of his former teachers Bradley and McTaggart), and his defense of what he
regarded as a “common sense” form of Philosophical Realism. In his 1925 essay A
Defense of Common Sense, Moore argued against idealism and skepticism
toward the external world, on the grounds that they could not give reasons to accept
their metaphysical premises that were more plausible than the reasons we have
to accept the common sense claims about our knowledge of the world that
skeptics and idealists must deny. He famously put this into dramatic relief
with his 1939 essay Proof of an External World, in which he gave a
common sense argument against skepticism by raising his right hand and saying:
“Here is one hand,” and then raising his left, and saying: “And here
is another,” then, concluding that there are at least two external objects
in the world, and therefore that he knows (by this argument) that an external
world exists. Not surprisingly, not everyone inclined to skeptical doubts found
Moore’s method of argument entirely convincing; Moore, however, defended his
argument on the grounds that skeptical arguments seem invariably to require an
appeal to “philosophical intuitions” that we have considerably less
reason to accept than we have for the common sense claims that they supposedly
refute. (In addition to fueling Moore’s own work, the Here is one hand
argument also deeply influenced Wittgenstein, who spent his last years working
out a new approach to Moore’s argument in the remarks published posthumously as
On Certainty.
Moore is
also remembered for drawing attention to a peculiar inconsistency involved in
uttering a sentence such as “It will rain, but I don’t believe it will”--
a puzzle which is now commonly called Moore's paradox. The puzzle arises
because it seems impossible for anyone to consistently “assert” such a sentence;
but there does not seem to be any “logical contradiction” between “It will
rain” and “I don’t believe that it will rain.”
In
addition to Moore’s own work on the paradox, the puzzle inspired a great deal
of work by Wittgenstein, who described the paradox as the most impressive
philosophical insight that Moore had ever introduced.
And
finally, Moore’s description of the principle of organic unity is
extremely straightforward; nonetheless, it is a principle that seems to have
generally escaped ethical philosophers and ontologists before his time:
The
value of a whole must not be assumed to be the same as the sum of the values of
its parts (Ethica §18).
According
to Moore, a moral actor cannot survey the “goodness” inherent in the various
parts of a situation, assign a value to each of them, and generate a sum in
order to get an idea of its total value. A moral scenario is a complex assembly
of parts, and its total value is often created by the relations between those
parts, and not by their individual value. The organic metaphor is thus very
appropriate: biological organisms seem to have emergent properties, which
cannot be found anywhere in their individual parts. For example, a human brain
exhibits a capacity for thought when none of its neurons exhibit any such
capacity. In the same way, a moral scenario can have a value far greater than
the sum of its component parts.
To
understand the application of the organic principle to questions of value it is
perhaps best to consider his primary example, that of a consciousness
experiencing a beautiful object. To see how the principle works, a thinker
engages in “reflective isolation”, that is, an act of isolating a given concept
in a kind of null-context, and determining its intrinsic value. We can easily
see that per sui, beautiful objects and consciousnesses are not very valuable
things; they may have some value but when we consider the total value of a
consciousness experiencing a beautiful object, it seems to exceed the simple
sum of these values (Principia Ethica 18:2).
Here ends our extended selection
on Moore’s ethics, which clearly demonstrates that, in the ethical field, his
position is solid as a legitimate heir of the great ethical philosophers of the
past.
No comments:
Post a Comment