Melissus of
Samos is of a far lesser stature than the other members of the Eleatic school,
and even by the kindest regard he does not measure up to his teacher
Parmenides. Nietzsche’s works have no mention of his name, and our History
of Philosophy of choice, by Bertrand Russell, is equally silent about him.
However, this man did exist, and he was a bona fide pre-Socratic, which qualifies
him for at least one short entry in this section.
The usually
unreliable yet absolutely indispensable Diogenes Laertius writes of him as both
a considerable thinker and a prominent citizen of his native Samos, who
commanded a fleet which surprisingly defeated the Athenians in 442 BC. Whether
Diogenes’ account can be trusted in this case is a minor matter, as we are
interested in Melissus the philosopher, and not for his military or political
prowess. As for whose pupil Melissus was, Diogenes names both Parmenides and
Heraclitus as his teachers. Whereas the Parmenidean connection is generally
established as a fact, Melissus’ connection to Heraclitus is certainly
spurious, as the biographical dates for both do not seem to add up, even by
Diogenes’s own arithmetic.
Among
his extant Fragments, quoted by Simplicius, here are a few interesting
samples:
1. What was, always was, and always shall be. For, if it came into
being, necessarily, before its generation, there was nothing; so if there were
nothing, nothing at all would come from nothing. (This offhand denial of even the least possibility of creatio ex
nihilo clashes with the Christian doctrine, and thus, without making a
judgment as to who is right and who is wrong, one thing at least is clear that creatio
ex nihilo ought not to be dismissed so lightly as something impossible and
self-evidently false. Thus with the basic premise of the Melissian doctrine
formulated on such rationalistic ground, we can hardly expect from Melissus any
mystical solutions to the problem of the Genesis, which is of course a
deficiency. As for his general usefulness, see my closing comment. Having said
that, Melissus’ deficiencies may make him less interesting than the greatest
pre-Socratics, yet this is not a good reason to deny him his pre-Socratic
value. A collection of ancient coins may contain items of sharply unequal
value, but none of them ought to be discarded merely on that comparative basis.
His extant fragments, even if somewhat deficient, allow us to follow Melissus’
line of thinking, which is in itself a treasure trove for modern thinkers.)
8i. If there were many things, they would have to be such as I say
the one is. For if there is earth, and water, and air, and fire, and iron, and
gold, and one living and another dead, and again black and white, and all the
other things which people say are real, if indeed there are these and we see
and hear correctly, each must be such as we first decided, and they cannot
change or become different, but each is always as it is. (We may easily challenge Melissus’ logic in these
fragments, perhaps too easily, but before we dismiss it altogether, let us
remember that the outward silliness of Zeno’s famous Paradoxes has never
prevented them from being studied in all seriousness for well over two thousand
years, admittedly putting philosophers at a considerable loss to prove that the
proposition that an athletic man can never overtake a tortoise in a race, if
that tortoise has been given even the slightest of handicaps over him…)
8ii. But, as we say that we see and hear and perceive correctly,
and yet it appears to us that the hot becomes cold, and the cold hot, and the
hard soft, and the soft hard, and the living dies and there is birth from what
is not living, and all these things change around and what a thing was and what
it is now are not the same, but iron, which is hard, is rubbed away by contact
with the finger, and also gold and stone, and whatever seems to us to be
strong, and from water come earth and stone, so it happens that we do not
understand what there is.
9. So if it exists it must be one; and being one, it could not have
body. If it had any thickness, it would have parts, and would no longer be one.
10. If what exists is divided, it moves: and if it moves, it would
not exist.
His
arguments are generally derivative from Parmenides, and, where they are
original, they do not add any substance to the Parmenidean doctrine, except to
assert that the One is both infinite and eternal, which has a good
point, but the demonstration is faulty, thus making it demonstrably unhelpful
in unraveling some of the finer mysteries within the Parmenidean puzzle.
No comments:
Post a Comment