In
the G8 (‘Group of Eight’) of Nietzsche’s “pre-Socratic” philosophers (actually,
from Thales to Socrates), Parmenides immediately follows Nietzsche’s darling Heraclitus,
and occupies some considerable space in his Philosophy in the Tragic Age of
the Greeks.
Parmenides
is the antipode of Heraclitus, and as such he comes out in Nietzsche’s work:
While each word of Heraclitus expresses the pride and the majesty
of truth, but truth grasped in intuitions, rather than attained by the rope
ladder of logic, while--in Sibylline rapture--Heraclitus gazes, but does not
peer, knows, but does not calculate, his contemporary Parmenides stands
beside him as the counter-image, likewise expressing a type of truth-teller,
but one formed of ice, rather than fire, pouring cold piercing light all
around. Once in his life, Parmenides, probably at a fairly advanced age, had a
moment of purest, totally bloodless abstraction, unclouded by any reality. This
moment— un-Greek as no other in the two centuries of the Tragic Age—whose
product is the doctrine of Being, became for Parmenides’ own life the boundary
stone that separates two periods. At the same time, however, this moment
divides all pre-Socratic thinking into two halves. The first may be called the Anaximandrian
period, the second,-- the Parmenidean period proper. The first,
older period of Parmenides’ own philosophizing still bears some Anaximandrian
traces; it has brought forth an organized philosophical-physical system in
answer to Anaximander’s questions. When later Parmenides was seized by that icy
tremor of abstraction, and came face to face with his utterly simple
proposition as to being and non-being, all his own previous teachings joined
the rubbish-heap of the older doctrines. Still, he seems not to have lost every
trace of paternal goodwill toward the sturdy and well-made child of his youth,
and he helped himself out by saying, “There is only one right way, to be
sure, but if one wishes for a change, to try another, then, my former view, as
to quality and consistency, is the only right one.” Guarding himself by
this approach, he awarded his former physical system a dignified and extensive
position, even in that great poem On Nature, that was meant to proclaim
his new insight as really the only way of truth. This paternal solicitude, even
considering that it might have crept in by error, presents the only trace of
human sentiment in a nature wholly petrified by logical rigidity and almost
transformed into a thinking machine.
Thus,
according to Nietzsche, both Heraclitus and Parmenides started their positions
from Anaximander’s big question, but took entirely opposite routes. Parmenides compared qualities, and believed that he found
them not equal, but divided into two rubrics. Comparing, for example, light and
dark, he found the dark but the negation of the light. Thus, he
differentiates between the positive and negative qualities, while seriously
attempting to find and note this basic contradictory principle throughout all
nature. His method was like this: he took several contradictories, such as
light and heavy, rare and dense, active and passive,--- and held them against
his original model contradictories light and dark. Whatever corresponded to
light, was then the positive quality, whatever corresponded to dark, the
negative. Taking heavy and light, for example, light [in the sense of weightless]
was apportioned to light, heavy to dark, and thus heavy seemed to him
the negation of weightless, however, weightlessness seemed a positive quality.
The method exhibits a defiant talent for abstract-logical procedure, closed
against all influences of sensation. Because heaviness seems to urge itself
upon the senses as a positive quality; this did not prevent Parmenides from
labeling it as a negation. He also designated earth against fire, cold against
warm, dense against rare, feminine against masculine, and passive against
active, to be negatives. Thus before his gaze our world divides into two
spheres: one characterized by light, fieriness, warmth, weightlessness,
rarefaction, activity, and masculinity, the other, by the opposite, negative
qualities. The latter really express only the lack, the absence of the former.
Instead of the words ‘positive’ and ‘negative’ he used the absolute terms
‘existent’ and ‘nonexistent.’ Now he had arrived at the principle, Anaximander
notwithstanding, that our world contains something which is existent, as well
as something which is nonexistent. The existent should therefore not be sought
outside the world and beyond our horizon. Right here before us, everywhere, in
all coming-to-be, there is contained an active something which is existent.
But now he was left with the task of formulating a more exact
answer to the question “What is coming-to-be?” —and here we shall enter
the fog, the mysticism of qualitas occulta and even, just a little, the
realm of mythology. Parmenides, like Heraclitus, gazes at universal
coming-to-be and at impermanence, and he can interpret passing away only as
though it were a fault of nonexistence. For how could the existent be guilty of
passing away?! But coming-to-be, too, must be produced with the help of the
nonexistent, for the existent is always there. Of and by itself it couldn’t
come-to-be nor could it explain coming-to-be. Hence coming-to-be as well as
passing away would seem to be produced by the negative qualities. But, since
that which comes-to-be has a content that is lost in the process of passing
away, it presupposes that the positive qualities (for they are the essence of
such content), likewise participate in both processes of change. To sum up, we
now have the dictum “For coming-to-be, both the existent and the nonexistent
are necessary; when they interact, we have a coming-to-be.” But how are the
positive and the negative to get together? Shouldn’t they forever flee each
other, as contradictories, and thus make all coming-to-be impossible?…
Parmenides now appeals to a qualitas occulta, the mystic tendency of opposites
to attract and unite, and he symbolizes the opposition in the name of Aphrodite
and the empirically well-known relationship between masculinity and femininity.
The power of Aphrodite weds the opposites, existent with nonexistent! Desire
unites the contradictory and mutually repellent elements: the result is coming-to-be.
When desire is satiated, inner opposition and hatred drives the existent and
the nonexistent apart once more, and man says, “All things pass.”
Now,
here is a profoundly poetic Nietzschean description of Parmenidean philosophy,
as poetic as it can get, and despite its poetic verbosity non-essential in a
dried-out synoptical abstract, I cannot resist the great temptation of quoting
from it at some length, even if it may bloat my entry beyond reasonable
limits.---
And now, whenever Parmenides glances backward, at the world of
come-to-be, he becomes angry with his eyes for so much as seeing come-to-be, with
his ears for hearing it. “Whatever you do, do not be guided by your dull eyes,
nor by your resounding ears, nor by your tongue, but test all things with the
power of your thinking alone!” Thus he accomplished the momentous first critique
of man’s apparatus of knowledge, an inadequate critique as yet, but doomed to
bear dire consequences. By wrenching apart the senses and the capacity for
abstraction, he demolished intellect, encouraging man to indulge in the
erroneous distinction between spirit and body, which, since
Plato, lies upon philosophy like a curse. All sense perceptions, says
Parmenides, yield but illusions. And the main illusoriness lies in the pretense
that the nonexistent coexists with the existent, that Becoming, too, has Being.
All the manifold colorful world known to experience, all the transformations of
its qualities, all the orderliness of its ups and downs, are cast aside mercilessly,
as mere semblance and illusion. Nothing may be learned from them. All effort
spent upon this false deceitful world which is futile and negligible, faked
into a lying existence by the senses, is therefore wasted. When one makes as
total a judgment as does Parmenides about the world as a whole, one is no
longer a scientist. One’s sympathy toward phenomena atrophies; there develops a
hatred for phenomena including oneself, a hatred for being unable to get rid of
the everlasting deceitfulness of sensation. Henceforth, the truth shall live
only in the palest, abstracted generalities, in the empty husks of the most
indefinite terms, as though in a house of cobwebs. And beside such truth now
sits our philosopher bloodless like his abstractions in the spun out fabric of
his formulae. While a spider at least wants blood from its victims the
Parmenidean philosopher hates most the blood of his victims, the blood of the
empirical reality, sacrificed and shed by him.
This
entry would have been sorely incomplete had we failed to quote another passage,
this time from a late-late Nietzsche, namely, from his Wille zur Macht (#539),
where he chooses to contrast his own paradox to a Parmenidean one: “Parmenides said, ‘One cannot think of what is not’;
we are at the other extreme, and say, ‘What can be thought of, must
certainly be a fiction.’”
This
is indeed a paradox, for we are familiar with another wording of the
Parmenidean maxim: “What cannot be
thought of, does not exist.” To put the two maxims side by side, we come up
with yet another quasi-absurdity: “All
that exists is fiction.” Let us not play the juvenile rationalist who
dismissed all fairytales and fables on the grounds that toads never talk like
humans. Here is a delightful intellectual challenge that must not be dismissed,
because without such food for thought our brain will starve to death…
As
always, Nietzsche displays a profound depth and originality of his thinking,
but the fact that he finds a fertile ground for his original thinking in
Parmenides, whether he disagrees with him or not, serves as an appropriate tribute
to that great Greek, whose genius for stimulating ensuing millennia of advanced
philosophical thinking is again demonstrated in Nietzsche’s final tribute.
No comments:
Post a Comment