I remember how at a very young
age I was reading a child’s adaptation of Homer’s Iliad, and replaying
the Graeco-Trojan War with toy soldiers on the floor of my room. One of the
things which struck me the most then was the fact that I was unable to identify
one side as “us” and the other as “them.” I liked Achilles, but disliked
Odysseus; I liked Hector, but disliked Paris… Ironically,
switching from the Iliad to the Odyssey, the person of Odysseus
became much more to my liking. How could this be possible? My mother
explained it to me, by saying that there can be good people fighting against
each other in a war, using Mikhail Bulgakov’s White Guard as an example.
(She was virtually repeating to me word-for-word what Stalin had previously
told my father Artem about Bulgakov’s great work.) But here is my friend
Nietzsche talking about the Iliad along the same lines, and answering my
question in his own inimitable manner.
The following Nietzschean
passage, constituting Menschliches 45, is of immense psychological value
both in application to particular individuals, and to society as a whole. It is
well deserving to be quoted in full:
“Dual prehistory of good and evil. The concept of good and evil has a dual prehistory. First,
in the soul of the ruling clans and castes. The man who has the power to
requite goodness with goodness, and evil with evil, and really does practice
requital by being grateful and vengeful, is called “good.” The person
who is unpowerful, and cannot requite, is taken for bad. As a good man, one
belongs to the “good,” a community that has a communal feeling, because
all the individuals are entwined by their feeling for requital. A bad man
belongs to the “bad,” to a mass of abject, powerless men who have no
communal feeling. The good men are a caste; the bad men are a multitude, like
particles of dust. Good and bad are for a time the same as noble and low,
master and slave. Conversely, one does not regard the enemy as evil: he can
requite. In Homer, both the Trojan and the Greek are good. Not he who does harm
to us, but he who is contemptible is considered bad. In the community of the
good, goodness is hereditary; it is impossible for a bad man to grow out of
such good soil. Should one of the good men nevertheless do something unworthy
of good men, one resorts to excuses; one blames God, for example, saying that
he struck the good man with blindness and madness.
“Then,
in the souls of the oppressed, the powerless. Here, all other human beings are
considered bad, cruel, inconsiderate, exploitative, crafty, whether they be
noble or base. Evil is their epithet for man, indeed, for every possible living
being, even, for example, for a god. Human, Divine mean the same
as devilish, evil. The signs of graciousness, helpfulness, pity are anxiously
considered as malice, as preludes to a disastrous conclusion, soporifics, and
craft, in short, as refined malice. With such a state of mind in the
individual, a community can hardly come about at all, or at most in the crudest
form. Wherever this conception of good and evil predominates, the ruination of
individuals, their tribes and races, is near.
“Our
current morality has grown on the soil of the ruling tribes and castes.”
Aside from the multitude of
delightful nuances, which this passage contains, we may particularly note that
the ability to requite goodness with goodness and evil with evil, according
to the cultural traditions of such tribes, is the foundation of social
justice, and consequently, only in such societies where this concept clearly
predominates is social justice possible. It is therefore perfectly correct to
point out as Nietzsche does that our current morality [being
justice-centered] has grown on the soil of the ruling tribes and castes,
whereas the morality of the oppressed recognizes no justice, and therefore, in
all historical cases when the oppressed had actually taken power, it had always
been transitional, and never institutional. In the best familiar to me case of
the Russian Bolshevik Revolution of 1917, it was the morality of the Russian
Intelligentsia, which triumphed with Stalinism, the morality of the
well-educated ruling elite. One may be horrified by the cruel practices of
Stalinism, but one cannot deny it a consistent and essentially moral view, and
likewise practice of justice.
No comments:
Post a Comment