Friday, September 18, 2015

PHENOMENOLOGY TRANSCENDING THE SPIRIT.


The title of this entry is unabashedly ironic. First in 1807 was Hegel’s groundbreaking Phänomenologie des Geistes. Then, a full century later, Edmund Husserl invented phenomenology. Is this supposed to mean that Husserl somehow transcended Hegel’s own phenomenology, or were they talking about different things? By asking this trick question, I am not entering a philosophical discussion about apples and oranges (comparing these two is by no means a meaningless endeavor, as long as it is properly done, from the philosophical point of view), but only launching the special entry on Husserl, who certainly deserves one, as the acknowledged inventor of a philosophical something.

The philosophical stature of Edmund Husserl (1859-1938) can be argued about, but it is his invention of the new philosophical discipline called phenomenology, and notably his last major work The Crisis of European Sciences and Transcendental Phenomenology, left unfinished at the time of his death in 1938, which make him a curious figure to comment about, and so we shall.

Husserl was a Jewish-born German philosopher who converted to Lutheranism in 1887, that is, long before it would become politically expedient. Yet in 1933 he was still dismissed from his university teaching position because of his Jewish roots.

His philosophy offers a peculiar combination of totally derivative concepts and his original arrangements of them, resulting in his creation of a new philosophical discipline, under the unoriginal title of phenomenology. (As a matter of fact, phenomenology can be considered a technical term. My Webster’s Dictionary has these two definitions: [1.] The science dealing with phenomena as distinct from the science of being [ontology]; [2.] The branch of a science that classifies and describes its phenomena without any attempt at explanation.)

(The following differently-colored note on Husserl’s contribution to the science of philosophy is derived from general reference sources, and it is presented here merely as an important element of reader’s edification on the matter at hand.)

Although previously employed by Hegel, it was Husserl’s adoption of this term (circa 1900) that propelled it into becoming the designation of a philosophical school. As a philosophical perspective, phenomenology is its method, though the specific meaning of the term varies according to how it is conceived by a given philosopher. As envisioned by Husserl, phenomenology is a method of philosophical inquiry that rejects the rationalist bias dominating Western thought since Plato, in favor of a method of reflective attentiveness that discloses the individual’s “lived experience.” Loosely rooted in an epistemological device, called epoché, rooted in Skepticism, Husserl’s method entails the suspension of judgment while relying on the intuitive grasp of knowledge, free of presuppositions and intellectualizing. Sometimes depicted as the “science of experience,” the phenomenological method is rooted in intentionality (originally Franz Brentano’s term), which is now Husserl’s theory of consciousness. Intentionality represents an alternative to the representational theory of consciousness, which holds that reality cannot be grasped directly, because it is available only through perceptions of reality, which are representations of it in the mind. Husserl countered that consciousness is not “in” the mind, but rather conscious of something other than itself (the intentional object), whether the object is a substance or a figment of imagination (i.e. the real processes associated with and underlying the figment). Hence, the phenomenological method relies on the description of phenomena as they are given to consciousness, in their immediacy.

And finally the above-mentioned last work of Husserl, his Crisis of European Sciences and Transcendental Phenomenology is his contemplative answer to the deep crisis facing the intellectual world in the 1930’s, as a result of the “rise of barbarism.” Husserl connects it to what he sees as a pervasive misunderstanding of human reason, a misunderstanding that he tries to correct through his notion of the Lebenswelt, Life-world. The sciences, he says, can be given meaning only if they are founded on (his) phenomenology! Whether he is right or wrong is unimportant. At least he was successful in asking some useful questions, which is all that can be expected from a good philosopher.

(That last short paragraph would have been a proper conclusion to this entry, yet I cannot stop myself from making the following ironic observation. In my by now famous 1963 Webster’s Biographical Dictionary, there is a supershort article on Husserl, calling him “a German philosopher,” but giving no more details on him whatsoever. Why is that so? Frankly, my reader, I have no idea as to why! It is quite obvious that such a glaring neglect of an important philosopher has to mean something. Perhaps sometime in the future I may find it out…)

No comments:

Post a Comment