Wednesday, December 24, 2014

FEUERBACH OF THE MARX AND ENGELS FAME


Ludwig Andreas von Feuerbach (1804-1872) is not a household name in the Western world, but it was such to every Soviet college student, on account of his everlasting connection to Marxism, one of whose sources he was claimed to be. It is for this reason, if not for any other, that he deserves a special look in this section, and he naturally gets it.

Regrettably, our good friend Bertrand Russell virtually omits him from any kind of mention in his History of Western Philosophy, except for the following sentence in his chapter on Karl Marx:

“At the university he [Marx] was influenced by the still prevalent Hegelianism, as also by Feuerbach’s revolt against Hegel towards materialism…”

Feuerbach is frequently referred to as a bridge between Hegel and Marx, but this characterization is sorely inaccurate, as Marx did not require a bridge between himself and Hegel. More importantly than his young Hegelianism, it was Feuerbach’s dismissal of religion (shift from Hegel’s idealism to materialism), which can be represented as his principal influence on Marxism as an offshoot of Hegelianism. After all, religion (seen as the outward projection of man’s inner nature) was his main philosophical interest. I am of course at odds with such an understanding of religion, whose main significance, in my opinion, is cultural and social, and the phenomenon of personal faith is, as I believe, of a later, more anthropologically advanced origin.

Although Feuerbach is never counted among major philosophers in European history, there are implicitly made suggestions that he may be one. Along with Schopenhauer, Kierkegaard, Marx, and Nietzsche, he is seen as one of European philosophical outsiders who rebelled against the academic philosophy of the 19th century and thought of themselves as reformers and prophets of a new culture. (New World Encyclopedia) By placing him in such an illustrious company, the source boosts his importance by association, and, even though I do not find him fit to stand among the greatest, suggestions of this sort are rather significant.

Other than that, my Webster’s Biographical Dictionary gives him a short mention among the sons of Paul Johann Anselm von Feuerbach (1775-1833), German jurist and philosopher, specialist in criminology. The father is far less prominent in the history of philosophy, but he gets nearly twice as much space as his son… Being interested in this entry in the son only, we shall thus skip the father and his other sons, and focus on our Feuerbach only:

“[Feuerbach] Ludwig Andreas (1804-1872), philosopher, pupil of Hegel in Berlin; abandoned Hegelian idealism for a naturalistic materialism, subsequently attacked orthodox religion and immortality, concluded is the outward projection of man’s inward nature; author: Das Wesen des Christentums (1840), Das Wesen der Religion (1845), etc.”

The following portion comes from the Internet Wikipedia sources:

Feuerbach’s most important work is Das Wesen des Christentums (1841). In part I of his book, Feuerbach developed what he calls the true or anthropological essence of religion.” Treating of God in his various aspects “as a being of the understanding,” “as a moral being or law,” “as love,” and so on, Feuerbach talks of how man is equally a conscious being, more so than God, because man has placed upon God the ability of understanding. Man contemplates many things, and, in doing so, he becomes acquainted with himself. Feuerbach shows that in every aspect God corresponds to some feature or some need of human nature. If man is to find contentment in God, he must find himself in God.Thus God is nothing else than man: He is, so to speak, the outward projection of man’s inward nature. This projection is dubbed as a chimaera by Feuerbach, that God and the idea of a higher being is dependent upon the aspect of benevolence. A God who is not benevolent, not just, not wise, is no God. He goes on to contend that qualities are not suddenly denoted as divine because of their godly association. The qualities themselves are divine therefore making God divine, indicating that man is capable of understanding and applying meanings of divinity to religion and not that religion makes a man divine.
In part 2, Feuerbach discusses the false or theological essence of religion,i.e. the view that regards God as having a separate existence over against man. Hence arise various mistaken beliefs such as the belief in revelation which he believes not only injures the moral sense, but also poisons, nay destroys, the divinest feeling in man, the sense of truth,and the belief in the sacraments, such as the Eucharist, which is to him a piece of religious materialism of which “the necessary consequences are superstition and immorality.”
Part 2 comes to a crux by seemingly retracting previous statements. He claims that God’s only action is the moral and eternal salvation of man: thus man has in fact no other aim than himselfbecause man’s actions are placed on God. He also contradicts himself by claiming that man gives up his personality and places it upon God, who in turn is a selfish being. This selfishness turns onto man and projects man to be wicked and corrupt, that they are incapable of good,” and it is only God who is good, the Good Being.” In such a way Feuerbach detracts from many of his earlier assertions while showing the alienation that takes place in man by worshipping God. Feuerbach affirms that goodness is, “personified as God,” turning God into an object, because if God were anything but an object nothing would need to be personified upon him. The aspect of objects having previously been discussed; in that man contemplates objects and that objects themselves give conception of what externalizes man. Ergo, if God is good so then should be man because God is merely an externalization of man, because God is an object. However, religion shows that man is inherently corrupt. Feuerbach tries to lessen his inconsistency by asking if it were possible if, I could perceive the beauty of a superb picture if my mind were aesthetically an absolute piece of perversion?” Through such Feuerbach’s reasoning, it may not be possible, but it is possible, and he later states that man is capable of finding beauty.

Honestly, I am not a great fan of Feuerbach’s philosophy of religion. I guess that the only contribution that he may have made to Marxism was changing the tracks under the Hegelian train, from the idealistic track to the atheistic track. But to end this entry on a lighter note, here is a piece of some enlightening trivia. We are familiar of course with the expression “We are what we eat,” which, by the way, I used to find rather silly. But we are perhaps unfamiliar with the fact that this expression comes to us from the German rhyme: Mann ist was er isst, whose author happens to be none other than our Herr von Feuerbach! Having reexamined, on Feuerbach’s authority, the figurative significance of this dictum, I do not find it silly anymore.

 

No comments:

Post a Comment