For starters, here is the very
short (regrettably!) Cantor entry in
my Webster’s Biographical Dictionary:
“Cantor,
Georg. 1845-1919. German mathematician, born in St. Petersburg; professor,
Halle (from 1872). Developed a theory of irrational numbers, an arithmetic of
the infinite, and the theory of sets of points; he also introduced transfinite
numbers.”
Georg Ferdinand Ludwig Philipp
Cantor (1845-1919) was indeed a great German mathematician who developed all
these things. He also introduced the above-mentioned transfinite numbers, that
is, cardinal numbers or ordinal numbers which are larger than all finite numbers, yet do not necessarily qualify as absolutely infinite. The specific
distinction of “absolute infinity,”
also introduced by Cantor, identifies it with God, and thus his
mathematics explicitly transcends into religious philosophy. In order to better
understand what Dr. Cantor means by transfinite, as opposed to absolutely
infinite, here is what he says about it in a very succinct and
comprehensible fashion:
What
I assert and believe to have demonstrated… is that following the finite there
is a transfinite, that is an unbounded and ascending ladder of definite modes (compare this to Dèscartes’ distinctive pairs of definite-indefinite
and finite-infinite!), which by
their nature are not finite but infinite, but which, just like the finite, can
be determined by well-defined and distinguishable numbers. (Today, many mathematicians do not care much for Cantor’s
distinction, preferring the word infinite in all cases, but many still
use the term transfinite which I believe is a very useful term,
introducing an important nuance into the philosophical underpinnings of
mathematics.)
Cantor was by no means the only
mathematician who theologized and philosophized mathematics: the long history
of the blending of mathematics with philosophy explicitly starts with
Pythagoras, extending through Spinoza, Leibniz, and Kant into the twentieth
century. Cantor himself identified his position as a mathematician-philosopher.
It is therefore only natural for us to take him at his word, and rationalize
his appearance in this section on philosophical grounds.
There are some very interesting
facts about Cantor’s biography. He was born in Russia of a German father and
Russian mother, and although the family moved to Germany when he was just
eleven years old, Cantor retained a mystical spiritual affinity and nostalgia
for Russia throughout all his life.
He is also known for erratic
behavior that frequently cost him broken friendships. This fact is now
ascribed to a mental illness, periodically driving him into a depression, and
greatly complicating his professional and personal life. Bertrand Russell
treats Cantor in his History of Western Philosophy in the chapter
revealingly titled The Philosophy of Logical Analysis. But ascribing to
Cantor his philosophical credentials, we do not even need Cantor’s or Russell’s word for it. Any mathematician and scientist whose work involves
infinity, volens-nolens enters the domain of philosophy, and Cantor’s signature
endeavor dwelled in infinity as in his permanent residence.
Cantor’s specific area of
mathematics (incidentally, it is one of my favorite areas too!) is rather
esoteric for a reader not well-versed in it, but, in describing it, Russell
does a fairly good job of “Cantor-made-simple,” and for this reason his
Cantor passage is well-worth quoting:
…(Georg
Cantor) developed the theory of continuity and infinite number. Continuity until
he defined it had been a vague word, convenient for philosophers like Hegel,
who wished to introduce metaphysical muddles into mathematics. Cantor gave a
precise significance to the word, and showed that continuity, as he defined it,
was the concept needed by mathematicians and physicists. By this means a great
deal of mysticism, such as that of Bergson, was rendered antiquated. Cantor
also overcame the long-standing logical puzzles about the infinite number. Take
the series of the whole numbers from 1 onwards: this number must be an infinite
number. But now comes the curious fact: The number of even numbers must be the
same as the number of all whole numbers. Consider the two rows:
1, 2, 3, 4, 05, 06, ….
2, 4, 6, 8, 10, 12, ….
There is
one entry in the lower row for every one in the top row; therefore the number
of terms in these two rows must be the same, although the lower row consists of
only half the terms in the top row. Leibniz, who noticed this, thought it a
contradiction, and concluded that though there are infinite collections, there
are no infinite numbers. Georg Cantor, on the contrary, boldly denied that it
is a contradiction. He was right; this is only an oddity. Cantor defined an infinite
collection as one which has parts containing as many terms as the whole
collection contains. On this basis, he was able to build up a most interesting
mathematical theory of infinite numbers, thereby taking into the realm of exact
logic a whole region formerly given up to mysticism and confusion.
In the conclusion of this entry I
would like to introduce several Cantor quotes which underscore his brand of
bonding between mathematics and philosophy:
The
actual infinite as distinguished from
transfinite infinity arises in three
contexts: first, when it is realized in the most complete form, in a fully
independent otherworldly being, in Deo !!, where I call it the Absolute Infinite or simply the
Absolute; second when it occurs in the contingent created world; third when the
mind grasps it in abstracto as a mathematical magnitude, number or order type. Here
is a clear rationalization of Cantor’s invention of the term transfinite, to
set mathematics apart from theology, and in this philosophical aspect,
alongside others (such as logical, to set it distinctly apart), his
invention is both perfectly valid, and also highly commendable on all grounds.
The
essence of mathematics lies in its freedom. Again, the borderline
between mathematics and philosophy is crossed by the introduction of the
philosophical term freedom. The way I understand this statement, from my
subjective perspective, of course, is that once we realize that mathematics is
grounded in hypotheses, its progress lies in the expansion of the number of such
founding hypotheses, turning the mathematician into an inventor, a creator, a
thinker, a philosopher!
A set
is a Many that allows itself to be thought of as One. This is
perhaps the most spectacular and splendid example of a philosophical dictum,
bringing to mind nothing less than PreSocratica Sempervirens!
In
mathematics, the art of asking a question must be held of higher value than
solving it. Yes!!! But why so restrictive--- to mathematics only? We
are surely entitled to expand this judgment to all philosophical thinking (and,
“needless to say,” because the reader knows it already, I have always
subscribed to the expanded version of this statement). But, anyway, Georg
Cantor has already amply established his philosophical credentials to us by
now, and the reason for his mandatory inclusion into this section has
now been explained and justified beyond any doubt.
No comments:
Post a Comment