The great mathematician,
logician, philosopher and linguist Friedrich Ludwig Gottlob Frege (1848-1925)
once said that “Every good mathematician is at
least half a philosopher, and every good philosopher is at least half a
mathematician.” This may not be true in each and every case, but this is certainly true of Frege, whose
brilliant achievements not just in mathematics and logic, but, specifically, in
the philosophy of logic, philosophy of mathematics, and philosophy
of language, are of outstanding importance.
My first acquaintance with Frege
was at an early age through reading Bertrand Russell’s History of Western
Philosophy, where, in the chapter The Philosophy of Logical Analysis, Russell
(who happened to be one of very few people capable of appreciating Frege before
anyone else did) writes the following: “In
philosophy ever since the time of Pythagoras there has been an opposition
between the men whose thought was mainly inspired by mathematics and those who
were more influenced by the empirical sciences. Plato, Thomas Aquinas, Spinoza,
and Kant, belong to what may be called the mathematical party; Democritus,
Aristotle, and the modern empiricists, from Locke onwards, belong to the
opposite party. In our day, a school of philosophy has arisen which sets to
work to eliminate Pythagoreanism from the principles of mathematics, and to
combine empiricism with an interest in the deductive parts of human knowledge.
The aims of this school are less spectacular than those of most philosophers in
the past, but some of its achievements are as solid as those of the men of
science.
The
origin of this philosophy is in the achievements of mathematicians who set to
work to purge their subject of fallacies and slipshod reasoning. Russell now begins his list of such mathematicians with
Leibniz and Cantor. The next man of importance
was Frege, who published his first work (Begriffsschrift) in 1879, and his definition of “number” in 1884 (in The Foundations of Arithmetic); but in spite of the epoch-making nature of his
discoveries, he remained wholly without recognition until I drew attention to
him in 1903. It is remarkable that before Frege every definition of number that
had been suggested contained very elementary logical blunders. It was customary
to identify “number” with “plurality.” But an instance of
“number” is a particular number, say 3, and an instance of 3 is a
particular triad. The triad is a plurality, but the class of all triads which
Frege identified with the number 3 is a plurality of pluralities and number in
general of which 3 is an instance is a plurality of pluralities of pluralities.
The elementary grammatical mistake of confounding this with the simple
plurality of a given triad made the whole philosophy of number before
Frege a tissue of nonsense in the strictest sense of the term “nonsense.”
From
Frege’s work it followed that arithmetic and pure mathematics generally, is
nothing but a prolongation of deductive logic. This disproved Kant’s theory
that arithmetic propositions are “synthetic” and involve a
reference to time. The development of pure mathematics from logic was set forth
in detail in the Principia Mathematica, by Whitehead and myself.
Developing Russell’s explanation
of Frege’s historical accomplishment, I may paraphrase it by saying that, prior
to Frege, number was seen even by the greatest mathematical minds of all
time as a simple plurality, or a plurality of the first order, whereas three
men in a boat, or three oranges, or three sisters are all
such simple pluralities, while 3, as a number common to all, of them
becomes in reality a second-order plurality, and number as-such,
containing 3; 4; 5; 6; etc., becomes a third-order plurality. For someone
untutored in complex mathematical labyrinths, this distinction may not be such
a big deal at all. But once we enter into the realm of formal logic, Predicate
Calculus, and Quantification--- without which modern mathematics is
practically helpless, the Frege Revolution becomes comprehensible, and
it is fairly found comparable with the Cartesian Revolution of the seventeenth
century.
Talking about the Frege
revolution, I am fortunate enough to know what I am talking about, as
Frege, and his revolutionary mathematical logic, was one of my subjects at Moscow University. This is
obviously not the proper place to perplex the reader any further on either the
technicalities or even generalities of Frege’s mathematical logic, but one
thing must be repeated from the things said before, that here in this sphere,
associated with the broader sphere of logical analysis, mathematics and
philosophy merge into one, confirming, at least for these particular intents
and purposes, the wisdom of Frege’s observation, which has been condensed into
the title of this entry.
No comments:
Post a Comment