(It's a pity that one of
my favorite subjects: the Kantian Undinge,
currently subsists in this mostly unoriginal (largely derivative from Bertrand Russell) shape, but such is the fact,
and hopefully at a more propitious time this indignity will be properly
remedied. Meanwhile, I am posting this informative material now for the sake of
the continuity of the subject matter, considering that the need to include
Kant’s Space and Time in any Kant series
trumps the argument to the contrary.)
***
“Die Undinge,” “The Un-Things.”
This perfectly Halloweenish title refers to Kant’s designation of space and time. I wish the content of this entry were likewise Halloweenish,
but, come to think of it, it is, if the reader looks at it the right way.
Kant’s theory of space and time
is presented here largely using Bertrand Russell’s narrative. At this point,
this is clearly a stock entry, which is subsequently to be developed into my
personal take on this subject. (I suggest that when sufficiently simplified in
retelling, this subject is not as hard to grasp as it may seem, and I am
looking forward to presenting my original summary and commentary at the first
opportunity.)
According
to Kant, the outer world causes only the matter of sensation, whereas our own
mental apparatus orders this matter in space and time, supplying the concepts
by means of which we understand experience. Things in themselves, which are the
causes of our sensations, are unknowable; they are not in space or time and
they are not substances, nor can they be described by any of those other
general concepts, which Kant calls categories. Space and time, “Die Undinge, The Un-Things,”--- are subjective, part
of our apparatus of perception. But, because of this, we can be sure that
whatever we experience will exhibit the characteristics dealt with by geometry
and the science of time. Thus if you always wore blue spectacles, you could be
sure of seeing everything blue (this is not Kant’s illustration). Similarly,
since you always wear spatial glasses in your mind, you are sure of always seeing
everything in space: thus, geometry is a priori, in the sense that it
must be true of everything experienced, but we have no reason to suppose that
anything analogous is true of things in themselves, which we do not experience.
This is a tremendous psychological
insight on Kant’s part. Time and space, in his treatment, can be called our “prejudices,”
and looking at some other prejudices of ours (which constitute a massive
majority in our perception of everything around us, and much within us: even
the so-called open mind cannot escape from its own share of prejudices!)
we can understand two things: one, that many of our firmly held views are, in
fact, nothing better than prejudices; and two, that considering how strongly we
believe that space and time are objective realities, it is quite understandable
why some of our prejudices have such a tight hold on us.
Space
and time, Kant says, are not concepts; they are forms of Anschauung. (This German word is usually translated as intuition, but
such translation is not at all satisfactory!) There
are two forms of Anschauung: one for the outer sense, space, the other
for the inner sense, time.
To prove
that space and time are a priori forms, Kant has two classes of arguments, one
metaphysical, the other epistemological, or, as he calls it, transcendental. As
regards space, the metaphysical arguments are four in number:
1. Space
is not an empirical concept, abstracted from outer experiences, as space is
presupposed in referring sensations to something external, and external
experience is only possible through presentations of space.
2. Space
is a necessary presentation a priori which underlies all external
perceptions; for we cannot imagine that there should be no space, although we
can imagine that there should be nothing in space.
3. Space
is not a discursive or general concept of the relation of things in general:
there is only one space, of which what we call spaces are parts,
not instances.
4. Space
is represented as an infinite given magnitude, which holds within itself
all the parts of space. This relation is different from that of a concept to
its instances, and therefore space is an Anschauung, and not a concept.
The
transcendental argument about space is derived from geometry. Kant holds that
Euclidian geometry is known a priori, although it is synthetic, that is, not
deducible from logic alone. Geometrical proofs, he says, depend upon the
figures; we can see, for instance, that, given two intersecting lines at
right angles to each other, only one straight line at right angles to both can
be drawn through their point of intersection. Such knowledge, he thinks, is not
derived from experience. But the only way in which my intuition anticipates
what will be found in the object is if it contains only the form of my sensibility
antedating in my subjective all the actual impressions. The objects of sense
must obey geometry, because geometry is concerned with our ways of perceiving,
and therefore we cannot perceive otherwise. This explains why geometry,
although synthetic, is a priori and apodeictic.
The
arguments with regard to time are essentially the same, except that arithmetic
replaces geometry with the contention that counting takes time.
Coming now to criticizing Kant’s
theory, the four metaphysical arguments can be dismissed as too arcane and
subjective, while the transcendental argument does not hold water, as we now
know what Kant did not know, that there are actually two types of geometry, one
pure, which deduces consequences from axioms, without inquiring if the
axioms are true (this one is a priori, but not synthetic); and the other
derived from physics, in which the axioms are derived from measurements, and
are different from Euclid’s (this one is synthetic, but it is not a priori).
Generally speaking, we can talk about two kinds of space: one
subjective, and the other one objective, where Kant’s theories do not hold
water at all. With regard to time, there is no sense, in which perceptual time
can be subjective, and his theory of time falls apart right away.
At the same time, however, Kant’s
invalid arguments have historically generated a host of valid ones,
and in this sense he can be justly credited as the progenitor of all those
modern arguments that have promoted and enriched science, regardless of whether
his own arguments had been true or not.
No comments:
Post a Comment