Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel
(1770-1831) was an extremely important philosopher, both objectively and to me
personally, in view of my immense interest in the subject of totalitarian psychology
and totalitarian sociology, the serious and objective study
of which has been so far pitifully inadequate.
There are numerous references to
Hegel throughout several sections of this book, thereby underscoring his great
value, particularly for the studies of philosophy, history, and society.
Hegel’s influence on his and all
subsequent generations has been tremendous. He had his admirers: Bauer,
Feuerbach, Marx, and later Dewey and Sartre, among the better known, but,
ironically, some of the greatest of those who were deeply influenced by him
were to become his harshest critics. (Schopenhauer, Schelling, Kierkegaard,
and, to a much lesser, or milder, extent, Russell. I would not put
Nietzsche in the category of Hegel’s worst critics, as is often suggested: his
overall fairness to Hegel is all the more surprising, knowing how much he
admired Schopenhauer and respected his opinions!)
Before I even mention any
criticism of Hegel, which I will be doing in extreme moderation, here is a
great excerpt from Part One of Hegel’s Encyclopedia of Philosophical
Sciences, in which he presents by far the best defense of every refuted
philosophical system in the history of human thought. It is ironic, I must say,
that the very same philosopher who is virtually unanimously considered the most
difficult to comprehend, (in Russell’s words, Hegel’s
philosophy is very difficult--- he is, I should say, the hardest to understand
of all great philosophers), and some of whose obscure passages have
remained undeciphered even today, was able to come up with a thought so lucidly
and wonderfully expressed as this one:
A
much misunderstood phenomenon in the history of philosophy: the refutation of
one system by another, of an earlier by a later. Most commonly, the refutation
is taken in a purely negative sense to mean that the system refuted has ceased
to count for anything, has been set aside and done for. Were it so, the history
of philosophy would be, of all studies, most saddening, displaying, as it does,
the refutation of every system which time has brought forth. Now although it
may be admitted that every philosophy has been refuted, it must be in an equal
degree maintained that no philosophy has been refuted. And that in two ways.
First, every philosophy that deserves the name always embodies the Idea;
secondly, every system represents one particular factor or particular stage in
the evolution of the Idea. The refutation of a philosophy, therefore, only
means that its barriers are crossed and its special principle reduced to a
factor in the more complete principle that follows.
This definitive effort of
philosophy defending herself in the court of her critics is an excellent
preemptive strike against Schopenhauer’s repudiation of Hegel’s philosophy (as “...a colossal piece of mystification, which will yet
provide posterity with an inexhaustible theme for laughter at our times, that
it is a pseudo-philosophy, paralyzing all mental powers, stifling all real
thinking, and, by the most outrageous misuse of language, putting in its place
the most hollow, most senseless, most thoughtless, and as is confirmed by its
success, most stupefying verbiage…”), and to some extent of the
following introductory summary of Hegel in my otherwise much-loved
Bertrand Russell’s History of Western Philosophy (although I can argue
that the gist of what Russell says echoes Hegel’s defense of all philosophy):
“Hegel
was the culmination of the movement in German philosophy that started from
Kant. Although he often criticized Kant, his system could never have arisen if
Kant’s had not existed. (Exactly the same can be
said of Hegel’s philosophy and his legacy, and, most probably, with an even
stronger justification.) His influence, though
now diminishing, has been very great, not only or chiefly in Germany. At the
end of the nineteenth century, the leading academic philosophers, both in
America and Great Britain, were largely Hegelians. Outside of pure philosophy,
many Protestant theologians adopted his doctrines. His philosophy of history
profoundly affected political theory. Karl Marx, as everyone knows, was a
disciple of Hegel in his youth and retained in his own finished system some
important Hegelian features. (Now comes the famous
Russellian repudiation of Hegel’s doctrines, which I have underlined.) Even if (as I myself believe) almost all Hegel’s
doctrines are false, (now comes the implicit
retraction of the preceding criticism, which I have underlined as well) he still retains an importance which is not merely
historical, as the best representative of a certain kind of philosophy, which,
in others, is less coherent and less comprehensive.” Later, in the Hegel chapter, Russell continues with
the same pattern of a repudiation followed by a vindication: “…This was a mistake, and from this mistake arose the whole
imposing edifice of his system. (And now the
apotheosis of the conditional vindication, considering that the word interesting
is the highest compliment that can be paid to a philosopher or any other
creative thinker.) This illustrates the
truth that the worse your logic, the more interesting the consequences to which
it gives rise.
Having solicited such a sublime
compliment to Hegel from his alleged detractor Bertrand Russell, we shall now
proceed to the next entry in our Hegel series, which separately
addresses a certain unsolved mystery.
No comments:
Post a Comment