One of the most
complex philosophical questions, with regard to ethics, rises from the
perennial dilemma of how it is possible that good causes may produce bad
effects, and reversely, how bad causes may produce good effects. Considering
the absolute nature of goodness, the answer has to be "impossible," and
yet, in real life we come across the practical possibility of such theoretical
impossibility all the time.
My answer is
simple: look for the joker in the deck, for there must be a joker in the
deck! The circus magician does not really take the rabbit out of an
empty hat, the rabbit had to be there somewhere all the time, only we
could not see it.
In the Section
on Philosophy and Ethics, I have touched upon the ethical riddle
hidden inside the notion of the free choice, the most inconvenient of all gifts
of God to man, a catalyst for trouble. Free choice subsists in my view Jenseits
von Gut und Bรถse,
in this case, on the other bank of the mystical river, as an unknown
quality, in-itself, not subject to moral valuation. In order to reach
from cause to effect, both located on this side of the river, we have to
make a mystical trip to ‘the other side’ back and forth, something
comparable to the extranormal trips made by the characters in the Matrix movies.
Hence, the connection between our causes and effects becomes tainted, disconnected
by the trip Jenseits, and the frequent ethical disconnect between them
no longer poses a rational challenge to the absolute nature of goodness. (The
nature of evil, as I happened to point out elsewhere, is not absolute, in my
understanding, but only temporal.)
The preceding
theoretical rumination leads me now to Adam Smith and the subject of an
invisible hand.
Smith uses this
metaphor in Book IV of The Wealth of Nations, arguing that an individual
will employ his capital in foreign trading only if the profits available by
that method far exceed those available locally and that in that case it is
better for society as a whole that he does so: “But
the annual revenue of every society is always precisely equal to the
exchangeable value of the whole annual produce of its industry, or, rather, is
precisely the same thing with that exchangeable value. As every individual,
therefore, endeavors as much as he can, both to employ his capital in the
support of domestic industry, and so to direct that industry that its produce
may be of the greatest value; every individual necessarily labors to render the
annual revenue of the society as great as he can. He, generally, indeed,
neither intends to promote the public interest, nor knows how much he is
promoting it. By preferring the support of domestic to that of foreign
industry, he intends only his own security; and by directing that industry in
such a manner as its produce may be of the greatest value, he intends only his
own gain, and he is in this, as in many other cases, led by an invisible
hand to promote an end which was no part of his intention. Nor is it
always the worse for society that it was not part of it. By pursuing his own
interest he frequently promotes that of the society more effectually than when
he really intends to promote it. I have never known much good done by those who
affected to trade for the public good. It is an affectation, indeed, not very
common among merchants, and very few words need be employed in dissuading them
from it.” (IV .ii. 6-9)
The
paradox which Adam Smith is hereby promoting is that apparently out of the
totality of selfish motives of the enterprising individuals comes, as if
assisted by “an invisible hand,” an
end result most favorable to the public good.
In
The Wealth of Nations, Smith offers the following elucidation to
illustrate the simplicity of this principle:
"It is not from the benevolence of the butcher, the brewer, or the
baker that we expect our dinner, but from their regard to their own interest.
We address ourselves not to their humanity, (!) but to their self-love, and never talk
to them of our necessities, but of their advantages (what was the name of this little game again,
please?). Nobody but a beggar chooses to depend
chiefly upon the benevolence of their fellow-citizens." (I agree with
the last part, except that it is incomplete. Citizens of a commonwealth, or
state, if you like, are all parties to the same social contract, which is
supposed to give them the assurance that, leaving aside the self-interest of
their fellow-citizens, they can to an even greater extent depend upon the benevolence
of the state, without feeling themselves like beggars, into the bargain.)
With
this remarkable passage in mind (so remarkable that I have already used this
quotation elsewhere), a fairly simple comparison can be made between the
capitalist system (under which the vendor has to do his best to accommodate his
customer not for some noble or sentimental reason, but for the very selfish
reason of beating his competition) and the Soviet-style economic system
(where the salaried vendor’s incentive is largely lacking, except for saving
his neck from being branded as a saboteur, as a result of his poor service,
like it was the case under the highly efficient Stalinist system), to the
indisputable benefit of the capitalistic competitive system, but only if one
specific factor, such as this, is taken into consideration, to the exclusion of
all others. (Incidentally, a potentially unsurpassed, yet habitually
unappreciated source of personal motivation can be found in the individual’s
patriotic zeal, but this phenomenon is dismissed as a rare exception, rather
than a collective event, thus also dismissing the historical miracle of the
Stalinist society, which had transformed the USSR from relative backwardness
into a global superpower in the course of a single generation.)
The
situation changes dramatically, however, when we see our wonderful capitalist
merchant--- offering the best customer service available for the money--- being run
out of business by a giant corporation (like, say… Wal-Mart?), employing
salaried, undermotivated workers like in the latter days of the Soviet Union,
by offering so much cheaper prices that our small-business friend just cannot
compete… Adieu to the capitalist utopia of the neighborly butcher, the
smiley-faced brewer, and the self-loving baker!
Not
so simple, after all, is it? But here comes the expected qualification of the
self-love principle, courtesy of the Wikipedia
(blue font):
“Contrary to common misconceptions, Smith did not assert that all
self-interested labor necessarily benefits society, or that all public goods
are produced through self-interested labor. His proposal is merely that, in a
free market, people usually tend to produce goods desired by their
neighbors.” (Yes, and many drugs which usually
provide the cure to various diseases often have dangerous side effects, or
become ineffective, as the disease-producing organisms develop an immunity to
them!)
“...A very simple example of how the invisible hand is supposed to
work are checkout lines in a store. Each customer getting in line “selfishly”
chooses the shortest line, regardless of the other customers. Their utility
maximizing choice means that eventually customers, without the slightest
direction, and by following only their selfishness, form lines of the same
length, which is clearly the most efficient disposition.” (A beautiful argument that cannot be beaten, except
that its counterargument may be unbeatable too. This reminds me of Pantagruel’s
back-and-forth with Panourge, regarding the pros and cons of marriage. To each
pro-argument Pantagruel replies, “So, marry!” To each contra-argument he
reacts, “So, don’t!”)
And
here is the proof. Adam Smith himself frequently warns in The Wealth
of Nations about how the invisible hand can lead to disastrous outcomes. Apparently,
our laissez-faire providential remedy
may become a killer poison just like that, unless the physician big government
comes to the patient’s rescue. For instance:
“In the progress of the division of labor, the employment of the
far greater part of those who live by labor, that is of the great body of
people, comes to be confined to a few very simple operations, frequently to one
or two. But the understandings of the greater part of men are necessarily
formed by their ordinary employments. The man whose whole life is spent in
performing a few simple operations, of which the effects are, perhaps, always
the same, or very nearly the same, has no occasion to exert understanding or to
exercise invention in finding out expedients for removing difficulties, which
never occur. He naturally loses, therefore, the habit of such exertion, and
generally becomes as stupid and ignorant as it is possible for a human creature
to become. The torpor of his mind renders him not only incapable of relishing
or bearing a part in any rational conversation, but of conceiving any generous,
noble, or tender sentiment, and consequently of forming any just judgment that
concerns many even ordinary duties of private life. Of the great and extensive
interests of his country he is altogether incapable of judging, and unless very
particular pains have been taken to render him otherwise, he is equally
incapable of defending his country in war. The uniformity of his stationary
life corrupts the courage of his mind, and makes him regard with abhorrence the
irregular, uncertain, and adventurous life of a soldier. It corrupts even the
activity of his body, and renders him incapable of exerting his strength with
vigor and perseverance in any other employment than that to which he has been
bred. His dexterity at his own particular trade seems, in this manner, to be
acquired at the expense of his intellectual, social, and martial virtues. But
in every improved and civilized society this is the state into which the
laboring poor, that is, the great body of the people, must necessarily fall, unless
government takes some pains to prevent it.”
…Bravo,
Panourge! Bravo, Pantagruel!!!
No comments:
Post a Comment