Wednesday, July 9, 2014

IL PRINCIPE FIORENTINE. PART I.


[Also see my entry Machiavelli’s Disappointed Utopia in the Wishful Thinking section.]

Part I.

The great Niccolò Machiavelli (1467-1527) is the subject of this entry, and I can find nothing more fitting than to introduce him by quoting Bertrand Russell’s opening of his Machiavelli Chapter in his History of Western Philosophy:

“The Renaissance, though it produced no important theoretical philosopher, produces one man of supreme eminence in political philosophy, Niccolò Machiavelli. It is the custom to be shocked by him, he certainly is sometimes shocking. But many other men would be equally so, if they were equally free from humbug. His political philosophy is scientific and empirical, based upon his own experience of affairs, concerned to set forth the means to assigned ends, regardless of the question whether the ends are to be considered good or bad. When, on occasion, he allows himself to mention the ends that he desires, they are such as we can all applaud. Much of the conventional obloquy which attaches to his name, is due to the indignation of such hypocrites who hate the frank avowal of evil-doing. There remains, it is true, a good deal that is genuinely demanding criticism, but in this he is an expression of his age. Such intellectual honesty--- about political dishonesty--- would have been hardly possible at any other time, or in any other country, except perhaps in Greece, among men who owed their theoretical education to the sophists, and their practical training to the wars of petty states, which in Classical Greece as in Renaissance Italy were the political accompaniment of individual genius.”

In his glowing endorsement of Machiavelli’s honesty, Russell may have taken a cue from Francis Bacon’s comment along the same lines: “We are much beholden to Machiavelli and others, that write what men do, and not what they ought to do.” This is not altogether true, however, as, besides writing what men do, he is also writing about what they ought to do, as we can find easily in his Discorsi.

My own knowledge of Machiavelli started at a very early age of thirteen, not with his most famous work Il Principe, but with his historical Istorie Fiorentine and the utopian Discorsi. As I already mentioned in my earlier entry Machiavelli’s Disappointed Utopia in the Wishful Thinking Section, I owed my acquaintance with both to an old family friend and my personal mentor Maria Yevgenievna Grabar-Passek, editor of the splendid Soviet literary series Monuments of Historical Thought. (She actually recommended to me earlier editions of these works as her own Machiavelli project had not yet been realized by then. Also, she did not recommend his most famous work Il Principe to me at that time, probably deciding that its cynical quality may not have been quite appropriate for my young age.)

Machiavelli’s Istorie Fiorentine is undoubtedly a colossal Monument of Historical Thought, and it presents his historical genius as by no means inferior to the best in this genre, being both a literary masterpiece and a fine example of source scholarship, although some critics have complained that too much purely “political history” has been stuffed in it, and not enough “cultural history.” But then let us remember that Machiavelli was first and foremost a political philosopher, and his History, naturally, reflects primarily that side of his professional interest.

The popular impression of Machiavelli as an amoral cynic is the least likely conclusion one can draw from actually reading his great work Discorsi, which offers us incontrovertible proof that there is a large moral dimension to Machiavelli, the assumed amoralist. There are certain political-moral values which he holds dear: national independence and liberty above all, security and constitutional guarantee of law over whim. The best constitutions ought to distribute rights not only among the rich and the powerful, but also give a substantial share to the poor and powerless, or else political instability will necessarily ensue. Surprisingly to those who are not aware of it, Machiavelli gets the credit for being the first to formulate the doctrine of “checks and balances.” Princes, nobles and people must all have their part in the Constitution: then these three powers will keep each other reciprocally in check.As Bertrand Russell aptly notes, there are whole chapters (in the Discorsi) which seem almost as if they had been written by Montesquieu (!!!); most of the book could have been read with approval by an eighteenth-century liberal… The word ‘liberty is used as denoting something precious… The love of liberty and the theory of checks and balances came to modern times largely from the Renaissance, though also directly from antiquity (they came to Machiavelli himself, and through him to the Renaissance, naturally, also from antiquity). This aspect of Machiavelli is at least as important as the more famous “immoral” doctrines of Il Principe.

It is unfortunate that very few modern students of the American Constitution are aware of the fact that the term “checks and balances was coined by the Frenchman Montesquieu, but even fewer know that this idea comes from antiquity via Machiavelli. Repeating after Bertrand Russell that “this aspect of Machiavelli is at least as important as his more famous immoral doctrines,” it calls for a radical readjustment of our popular view of the great Florentine and of his political, philosophical, and ethical legacy.

End of Part I. To be continued tomorrow.

No comments:

Post a Comment