The
title of this entry contains a joke for those familiar with “nihilist”
Russian style, the word launched into its specific usage by Ivan Turgenev
and further made famous by Nietzsche. However, the word nihilist was not
original. The Latin word nihil has been appropriated on more than one
occasion, and by more than one event. In the history of philosophy, one
particular philosopher, the Greek sophist Gorgias, has been known as the nihilist, and this word as used in his case has
no connection to Russian revolutionary anarchism, except for the core meaning
of the word nihil, which means “nothing.” Later on in this entry
we shall see why Gorgias has been called a nihilist.
Before
we proceed, however, here is a short résumé of Gorgias’ life, offered mostly
for reference. He was born in Sicily circa 485 BC, and died in Thessaly in 380
BC, which means that he had lived the longest life of all the pre-Socratics,
and perhaps of all philosophers in history as well.
At
the advanced age close to sixty he came to Athens in 427 BC as the ambassador
of his native city, asking for Athenian aid against the city of Syracuse. His
mission was greatly successful, while his astounding eloquence won him the
admiration of the Athenians to such an extent, that he eventually made up his
mind to make the city of Athens his home base, traveling all around Greece.
He
was a master rhetorician, and his lessons for which he always charged a fee,
were highly prized. Among his suggestions to students was, for instance, that
you should respond to your opponent’s serious argument with a joke and always
respond to the opponent’s mockery with utmost seriousness. He insisted that he
was not teaching virtue and wisdom, but only the art of oratory. His fame was
great all over Greece, and statues of him were erected in many places. The
expression Gorgian figures, characterizing his bold innovations in
rhetoric, had become part of the Greek language.
Like
Protagoras and several other names, the name of Gorgias is easily
recognizable by any reader of Plato as the title character of one of his
dialogues. Plato is horrendously uncharitable to Gorgias, as he is to all
“sophists.” Much of his, and later Aristotle’s, animosity is explained by them
themselves, as they demolish the sophists for their practice of being paid for
teaching their skills to students. Plato and Aristotle were, of course, what we
can call “independently wealthy” and they could afford the luxury of teaching
for free. The sophists were not as financially fortunate, as those others, and
the money paid to them by their students was essential to their sustenance.
Contemptuously, both Plato
and Aristotle dismiss Gorgias as a quack philosopher, but they are badly unfair
to him. The philosophy of Gorgias is essentially a thoughtful repudiation of
Parmenidean philosophy, taken to the extreme in his most famous, and in all
probability the most important, philosophical work On Nature, or the
Non-Existent, which has come down to us in just two paragraphs transmitted
secondhand.
“How can anyone communicate the idea of color by means of words,
since the ear does not hear colors, but only sounds?” asks Gorgias and our first impulse will most probably
be to ridicule him from the elementary linguistic standpoint, yet, on second
thought his question is by no means incompetent. It is easy to correlate words
and colors to a person with normal vision, but it is a far more difficult task
when the person is either colorblind or totally blind, and here we find our language
communication skills failing us most miserably. Thus Gorgias is perfectly right
in putting this question the way he does, and his philosophical depth here is
already bearing fruit.
From
the first question Gorgias leads us through a series of complicated logical
acrobatics to the conclusion that Nothing exists; if anything existed, it could not be known; if
anything did exit, and could be known, still it could not be communicated.
This
nihilism of Gorgias is, naturally, absurd, but so was the Parmenidean
denial of change, so were Zeno’s paradoxes, etc. Such nonsense only proves my
point that, generally speaking, the greatest positive theories of the greatest
philosophers of history are nothing, if they alone should become our objects of
scrutiny, but what has the greatest merit here is their process of thinking,
which is, how their minds work, in propelling their geniuses towards
those supremely nonsensical conclusions. I am sure that all modern
mathematicians and theoretical scientists will readily concur with this conclusion.
No comments:
Post a Comment