Saturday, March 1, 2014

THE SIX SENSES AND THE SEVENTH SENSE OF PURPOSE


Aside from the customary six senses, that is, five plus ESP, there is also a seventh sense, which is the sense of purpose. This entry addresses all these senses, in the light of the atomistic teachings.

Let us start with the sixth sense, by simply acknowledging that the mind-bogglingly modernistic theories of the atomists, like all genius, can only be attributed to such ESP, or intuition, or whatever other exceptional name this sense is known under; and it will further suffice to say that among the citizens of the republic of geniuses, Leucippus and Democritus must have been allotted more than an equal share.

Having dispensed with the sixth sense, we now move to the first five, which, according to the atomists, are not to be completely trusted, yet neither discarded out-of-hand. In fact, there is a physicality in perception, some of this residing in the object of perception, thus being objective, whereas other features depending on the subject, thus being subjective.

In fact, there is no reality in the things of the world. Only the atoms and the void are real. The atoms move in the void, sometimes interlocking, when their shapes are compatible for it. But mostly atoms collide with each other, producing vortices in the process, and the vortices lead to the emergence of bodies and worlds, the latter being many, some on the ascendance, others in degeneration.

Now, the atomists claim that there are always thin layers of atoms shedding from the surfaces of the bodies and traveling through the air. Some of these eidola, or images, as they are called, impact our sense organs allowing us to perceive the bodies themselves. The reason why we ought not to trust our senses completely for a faithful perception of reality is that the eidola tend to become distorted, as they travel through the air, colliding with the atoms of the air.

The very first impression of this theory of perception is that it is designed to address just one of our senses, namely, vision, but the atomists try to go beyond one sense to embrace all five. The theory of taste, for one, asserts that taste sensations are produced in the tongue by the different shapes of the atoms. Some scratch the tongue, producing the impression of bitterness, others, being smooth, pleasantly roll over it, producing the impression of sweetness, etc.

As I said before, perception differs, in that it is twofold, objective and subjective. Such qualities as weight, density, and hardness are objective, whereas warmth, taste, and color are subjective. The former qualities, which are in the object, are open to our understanding, and are therefore more reliable than the qualities of the latter sort, which are not immanent in the object, but rely exclusively on our frequently faulty sensory perception, or on convention. In Democritus’ own words Sweet exists by convention, bitter by convention, color by convention; but in reality, atoms and the void alone exist. As for the two kinds of knowledge, that is, objective and subjective, Democritus says this: There are two forms of knowledge: one legitimate, one bastard. To the bastard sort belong all the following: sight, hearing, smell, taste, touch. The legitimate is quite distinct from this. When the bastard form cannot see more minutely, nor hear, nor smell, nor taste, nor perceive through the touch, then another, finer form must be employed. (Fragment 11, The Symmetry of Life.) This finer form is obviously deduction, or reasoning, and by no means induction. How Greek!

We are now left with the seventh sense, as I put it, that is, the sense of purpose, and confronting us here is a sea of controversy, or rather confusion of the later critics. To discuss this, I am again inviting Russell, in an abridged but still lengthy string of excerpts from The Atomists chapter in his History of Western Philosophy. (As the reader may remember from a number of previous similar cases, such quotations serve the purpose of ready reference, and thus are placed somewhat outside my original comments, at least until I am eventually able to sort these things out.)

“It was common in antiquity to reproach the atomists with attributing everything to chance. But they were, on the contrary, strict determinists, who believed that everything happens in accordance with natural laws. Democritus explicitly denied that anything can happen by chance. Leucippus (although his existence has been questioned), is known to have said one thing: “Naught happens for nothing, but everything happens from a ground and of necessity.” It is true that he gave no reason why the world should originally have been as it was; this, perhaps, might have been attributed to chance. But when, once the world existed, its further development was unalterably fixed by mechanical principles. Aristotle and others reproached [Leucippus] and Democritus for not accounting for the original motion of the atoms, but in this the atomists were more scientific than their critics. Causation must start from something, and, wherever it starts, no cause can be assigned for the initial datum… The atomists, unlike Socrates, Plato, and Aristotle, sought to explain the world without introducing the notion of purpose, or final cause. The “final cause” of an occurrence is an event in the future, for the sake of which the occurrence takes place. When we ask “Why?” concerning an event, we may mean either “What purpose did the event serve?” (requires a teleological explanation), or “What earlier circumstances caused this event?” (which requires a mechanistic explanation). Experience has shown that the mechanistic question leads to scientific knowledge, while the teleological one does not. The atomists asked the mechanistic question, and they gave a mechanistic answer. Their successors, until the Renaissance, were more interested in the teleological question, and this led science up a blind alley.

Bertrand Russell was a great man, but in this instance he is displaying a mixture of narrowness, bias, and even naiveté. Teleology is an essential part of scientific inquiry in several key fields, most significantly in modern politics, as I have been able to demonstrate elsewhere. It is therefore essential to any credible kind of philosophical inquiry, and apparently, Democritus, for one, realized that, but was unable to provide any credible teleological foundation for the atomistic theory, which is his demonstrable weakness. It does not, however, in any way diminish his and Leucippus’ dazzling achievement in developing all other aspects of the atomistic theory, and, in that sense, Russell is perfectly right. He is also right regarding the teleological obsession of science and philosophy until the Renaissance, but he ought not to extend his criticism beyond the reasonable deficiency of any obsession into the legitimate domain of teleology as such, and his eagerly promoted implication that teleology as such leads nowhere is patently wrong.

 

No comments:

Post a Comment