My readers have, by now, in all
probability, on my account, Lord Bertrand Russell among their household names.
It is no secret that just because Russell’s History of Western Philosophy has
been my favorite book on the history of philosophy since my early years, my
admiration for him has carried over into my old age. Not that it has been
undeserved outside the work in question. Russell is, perhaps, the greatest
thinker of the twentieth century, in my estimation, to which the next two
entries will bear witness. But rather than to start with the objectively
leading general philosophical entry, I have preferred to introduce the Bertrand
Russell series with a subjective throwback to the source of my initial
interest in him, which is his History. I will be making one single
concession to propriety, however, by starting with quoting the About the
Author note in my current copy of Russell’s selfsame history. So, here it
is:
Bertrand
Arthur William Russell, 3rd Earl Russell Viscount Amberley, born in
Wales on May 18, 1872, was educated at home and at Trinity College, Cambridge.
During World War I served four months in prison as a pacifist, where he wrote Introduction
to Mathematical Philosophy. In 1910 he published the first volume of Principia
Mathematica, with Alfred Whitehead. Visited Russia (as part of an official British delegation, in 1920, and
there he had the famous conversation with Lenin)
and lectured on philosophy at the University of Peking, in 1920-1921. Returned
to England, and there with his wife ran a progressive school for young children
in Sussex from 1927 to 1932. Came to the United States, where he taught
philosophy, successively, at the University of Chicago, UCLA, Harvard, and City
College of New York. (Returned to Cambridge in
1944.) Awarded the Nobel Prize for Literature
in 1950. Was active in disarmament, anti-nuclear testing movements, (protested against Vietnam War, Israeli occupation of
Palestine, Soviet invasion of Czechoslovakia, etc.), while continuing to add to his large number of published
books, which include Philosophical Essays 1910, The ABC Of Relativity, 1925,
Human Knowledge: Its Scope And Limits, 1948, Why I Am Not A Christian, 1957, and
The Autobiography Of Bertrand Russell, 1967, among many others.
Now the principal business of
this entry, which is Russell’s History of Western Philosophy. As a
tribute to his outstanding accomplishment, I will quote excerpts from his Preface,
which explains the principles that underlie this work:
Many
histories of philosophy exist, and it has not been my purpose merely to add one
to their number. My purpose is to exhibit philosophy as an integral part of
social and political life: not as isolated speculations of remarkable
individuals, but as both an effect and a cause of the character of the various
communities in which different systems flourished. This purpose demands more
account of general history than is usually given by historians of philosophy. I
have found this particularly necessary as regards periods, with which the
general reader cannot be assumed to be familiar. The age of scholastic
philosophy was an outcome of the reforms of the 11th century, and
these, in turn, were a reaction against previous corruption… Without some
amount of knowledge of the centuries between the fall of Rome and the rise of
the medieval Papacy, the intellectual atmosphere of the 12th and 13th
centuries can hardly be understood. In dealing with this period, as with
others, I have aimed at giving only so much general history as I thought
necessary for the sympathetic comprehension of philosophers in relation to the
times that formed them and the times which they helped to form.
One
consequence of this point of view is that the importance which it gives to a
philosopher is often not that which he deserves on account of his philosophic
merit. For my part, for example, I consider Spinoza a greater philosopher than
Locke, but he was far less influential; I have therefore treated him much more
briefly than Locke. Some men-- for example, Rousseau and Byron-- though not
philosophers at all in the academic sense, have so profoundly affected the
prevailing philosophical temper that the development of philosophy cannot be
understood if they are ignored. Even pure men of action are sometimes of
greater importance in this respect; very few philosophers have influenced
philosophy as much as Alexander the Great, Charlemagne, or Napoleon. Lycurgus,
if only he had existed, would have been a still more notable example.
In
attempting to cover such a vast stretch of time, it is necessary to have very
drastic principles of selection. I have come to the conclusion, from reading
standard histories of philosophy, that very short accounts convey nothing of
value to the reader; I have therefore omitted altogether (with few exceptions)
who did not seem to me to deserve a fairly full treatment. In the case of the
men whom I have discussed, I’ve mentioned what seemed relevant as regards their
lives and their social surroundings; I have even sometimes recorded
intrinsically unimportant details when I considered them illustrative of a man
or of his times.
The significance of Russell’s
stated approach to his History of Western Philosophy for my own effort
is to focus my attention in these future historical-philosophical
entries (implying that presently they are not in an adequate shape, being more
like stock entries, and requiring a major overhaul) not on a comprehensive picture,
which a combination of such histories may more or less adequately provide, but
on a few personal remarks, which make my contribution to the genre subjective, and
therefore unique. One way of looking at objectivity is as a multiplicity of
subjectivities, and in this sense, my personal subjectivity, being an extra one
in this multiplicity, acquires a demonstrable value.
No comments:
Post a Comment