Previously
we looked at the early works of Nietzsche the philologist, where unmistakable
traces of him as a philosopher can already be found. This entry deals with his
first undisputable philosophical work, where we can find unmistakable traces of
him as a philologist, which should not come as a surprise at all.
Nietzsche
has many interesting things to say about the pre-Socratics, and these have been
properly directed into the PreSocratica section. This entry is not so
much about these early Greek philosophers, as it is about their general
assessment by Nietzsche, and about how that assessment reflects on the
distinguished subject of the present section.
This
entry examines Nietzsche’s spiritual and intellectual connection to the great
pre-Socratics. Nietzsche is a philosopher-poet, and they were too! But there is
also an even finer connection, observed by Nietzsche, which places him
unmistakably in their company. Unlike Plato or Aristotle or other philosophers
who came after them and all of whom Nietzsche calls “hybrid types,” the
pre-Socratics are “pure type” specimens, and so is Nietzsche.
Reading
Nietzsche’s explanation of how the early Greek pre-Socratics stand out and
differ from those who succeeded them (in his 1872-1874 Philosophy in the
Tragic Age of the Greeks), I wonder which came first, the chicken or the
egg? Was Nietzsche himself already a pre-Socratic in spirit, when he introduced
himself to their bunch and found kindred spirits, or was his mind so much impressed
by the pre-Socratic patterns of thinking that he would subsequently abandon his
more or less traditional scholar’s career, and become, like them, an elemental
force of nature? The answer to this is probably as complex as the one about the
chicken and the egg, which is the reason why I have offered this rather beaten
analogy, which has more pertinence to this case than to most others, where it
is commonly used as a convenient cliché.
What
sets them all apart, in Nietzsche’s view, is their common defining correlation
not of a philosopher to a philosophy, but of a philosopher to his own unique
character.
“…Every nation is put to shame, if
one points out such a wonderfully idealized company of philosophers as that of
the early Greek masters, Thales, Anaximander, Heraclitus, Parmenides, Anaxagoras,
Empedocles, Democritus and Socrates. All these men are integral, entire and
self-contained and hewn out of one stone. Severe necessity exists between their
thinking and their character. They are not bound by any convention, because at
that time no professional class of philosophers and scholars existed.”
In
other words, looking at each of these men, we see particular individuals,
rather than representatives of particular schools of philosophy, as we would
see, for instance, in the persons of Plato and Aristotle. Even though, these
two giants had created their distinctive schools of Platonism and
Aristotelianism, the fact of the emergence of such philosophical schools has a
faint effect of de-personalizing the school founders. We as students of
philosophy become more involved with the schools than with the persons who
created them, and the difference here is more than a nuance. Our tête-à-tête
with a school, being essentially impersonal, pushes us toward academism, to
use the extremely apt Platonic word, rather than to the untrodden path of
original, elemental thinking. Here is Nietzsche again:
“They all stand before us in
magnificent solitude as the only ones who then devoted their life exclusively
to knowledge. They all possess the virtuous energy of the Ancients
whereby they excel the later philosophers in finding their own form and in
perfecting it by metamorphosis in its minutest details and general aspect. For
they were met by no helpful and facilitating fashion. Thus, together they form
what Schopenhauer, in opposition to the Republic of Scholars, calls a Republic
of Geniuses; one giant calling another across the arid intervals of ages, and
undisturbed by a wanton noisy race of dwarfs creeping about beneath them the
sublime intercourse of spirits continues.”
Next,
Nietzsche makes a delightfully insightful observation how a whole nation can be
seen not through a generalized abstract notion, but through an intellectual
intercourse of particular individuals. The soul of a nation can be seen like a
reflection of the moon in the lake of an individual soul (this metaphor is
mine).
“Of this sublime intercourse of
spirits, I have resolved to relate those items, which our modern hardness of
hearing might perhaps hear and understand; meaning, certainly, the least of
all. It seems to me that those old sages from Thales to Socrates have discussed
in that intercourse, although in its most general aspect, everything that
constitutes for our contemplation the peculiarly Hellenic. In their
intercourse, as already in their personalities, they express distinctly the
great features of the Greek genius, of which the whole of Greek history is a
shadowy impression, a hazy copy, which, consequently, speaks less clearly. If
we could rightly interpret the total life of the Greek nation, we should ever
find reflected only that picture which in her highest geniuses shines with more
resplendent colors.”
Now
is the right moment for Nietzsche to introduce one of his most significant
leitmotifs:
“…Other nations have their Saints,
the Greeks have Sages. Rightly it is said that a nation is characterized not
only by her great citizens, but rather by the manner in which she recognizes
and honors them. In other ages, the philosopher is an accidental solitary
wanderer in the most hostile environment,-- either slinking through or pushing
through with clenched fists. With the Greeks, though, the philosopher is not
accidental; when in the Sixth and Fifth centuries, amidst the most frightful
dangers and seductions of secularization, the philosopher appears and steps
forth from the cave of Trophonios into the very midst of luxuriance, the
discoverers’ happiness, the wealth and the sensuousness of the Greek colonies,
then we perceive that they come as noble warners for the same purpose for which
in those centuries Tragedy was born and which the Orphic mysteries in grotesque
hieroglyphics give us to understand. The opinion of those philosophers on Life
and Existence means much more than a modern opinion, because they had before
themselves Life in a luxuriant perfection, and because with them, unlike us,
the sense of the thinker was not muddled by the disunion engendered by the wish
for freedom, beauty, fullness of life, and the love for truth that only asks:
What is the good of Life at all? The mission which the philosopher has to discharge
within a real Culture can’t be clearly conjectured out of our circumstances and
experiences, for the simple reason that we have no such culture. It is
only a Culture like the Greek Culture that can answer the question, as
to that task of the philosopher, only such a Culture can justify philosophy,
because such a Culture alone knows, and can demonstrate, why and how the philosopher
is not an accidental chance wanderer, driven now hither, now thither. There is
a steely necessity, which fetters the philosopher to a true Culture: but what
if this Culture does not exist? Then, philosophers are incalculable and,
therefore, terror-inspiring comets, whereas in the favorable case, they shine
as the central star in the solar system of Culture. It is for this reason
precisely that the Greeks justify the philosopher, because with them they are
no comets.”
Eventually,
in his broad preamble, Nietzsche elaborates on his preference for the pre-Socratic
philosophers over the universally acknowledged giants of Greek philosophy, and
I just cannot for the sole sake of brevity leave out this supremely significant
and revealing passage:
“After such contemplations, it will
be accepted without offense if I speak of the pre-Platonic philosophers as of a
homogeneous company, and devote this paper to them exclusively. Something quite
new begins with Plato; or it might be said with equal justice that in
comparison with that Republic of Geniuses from Thales to Socrates, the
philosophers since Plato lack something essential.
“Whoever wants to express himself
unfavorably about the older masters may call them one-sided, and their Epigones
with Plato as head, many-sided. Yet it would be more just and unbiased to conceive
of the latter as philosophic hybrid characters, and of the former as the pure
types. Plato himself is the first magnificent hybrid character, and as such
finds expression as well in his philosophy as in his persona. In his ideology
are united Socratic, Pythagorean, and Heraclitean elements, and, for this
reason, it is not a typically pure phenomenon. As a person, too, Plato mingles
the features of the royally secluded, all-sufficing Heraclitus, of the
melancholy compassionate and legislatory Pythagoras, of the psycho-expert
dialectician Socrates. All later philosophers are hybrid characters; wherever
something one-sided does come into prominence with them, as in the case of the
Cynics, it is not type, but caricature. Much more important, however, is the fact
that they are founders of sects, and the sects founded by them are all
institutions in direct opposition to the Hellenic culture and to the unity of
its style prevailing up to that time. In their own way, they seek a redemption,
but only for the individuals, or, at the best, groups of friends and disciples,
closely connected with them. The activity of the older philosophers tends,
although they were unconscious of it, towards a cure and purification on a
large scale; the mighty course of Greek culture is not to be stopped; terrible
dangers are to be removed out of the way of its current; the philosopher
protects and defends his native country. Now, since Plato, he is in exile, and
conspires against his fatherland.”
Nietzsche’s
preamble ends with a half-hearted lament against the Fate, that left us with so
precious little to delight in, as far as the extant works of the pre-Socratics
have been able to reach us. Rather than retell what he says, it is best to
quote him again:
“It is a real misfortune that so very
little of those older philosophic masters has come down to us, and that all
complete works of theirs are withheld from us. Involuntarily, on account of
that loss, we measure them according to wrong standards and allow ourselves to
be influenced unfavorably towards them by the mere accidental fact that Plato
and Aristotle never lacked appreciators and copyists. Some people presuppose a
special providence for books, a “fatum libellorum.” Such a providence, however,
would, at any rate, be a very malicious one, if it deemed it wise to withhold
from us the works of Heraclitus, Empedocles’ wonderful poem, and the writings
of Democritus, whom the ancients put on a par with Plato, whom he even excels
as far as ingenuity goes, and as a substitute put into our hand Stoics,
Epicureans and Cicero. Probably the most sublime part of Greek thought and its
expression in words is lost to us; a fate which will not surprise the man who
remembers the misfortunes of Scotus Erigena or Pascal, and who considers that
even in this enlightened century, the first edition of Schopenhauer’s Die Welt
Als Wille Und Vorstellung had become wastepaper. If somebody will presuppose a
special fatalistic power with respect to such things he may do so and say with
Goethe: “Let no one complain about and grumble at things vile and mean,-- they are
the real rulers,-- however much this be gainsaid!” In particular they are far
more powerful than the power of truth, Mankind very rarely produces a good
book, in which-- with daring freedom-- is intonated the battle song of
truth, the song of philosophic heroism; and yet whether it is to live a century
longer or to crumble and molder into dust and ashes, depends on the most
miserable accidents, on the sudden mental eclipse of people’s heads, on superstitious
convulsions and antipathies, finally, on fingers not too fond of writing, or
even on eroding bookworms and rainy weather. But we shall not lament, but,
rather, take the advice of the reproving and consolatory words, which Hamann
addresses to scholars who lament over lost works:
“Wouldn’t the artist who succeeded in throwing a lentil through the
eye of a needle have sufficient, with a bushel of lentils, to practice his
acquired skill? One would like to put this question to all scholars who do not
know how to use the works of the Ancients any better than that man used his
lentils.” It may be added in our case that not one more word, anecdote or date
needed to be transmitted to us than has indeed been transmitted, indeed, that
even much less might have been preserved for us, and yet, we should have been
able to establish the general doctrine that the Greeks justify philosophy.”
I
will not be so presumptuous as to jump into agreeing with Nietzsche on the
impeccable intellectual taste and spiritual nobility of the Ancient Greeks in
treating their greatest thinkers as a superior caste. After all, it is very
unfortunate and, indeed, rather suspicious that the works of the pre-Socratic
philosophers had not survived the “annorum series et fuga temporum” in
a much larger volume, if not in their entirety. But I am completely with
Nietzsche in turning this Greek experience into a monumental history of
the greatness of the Ancient Greek spirit, as a lesson to subsequent generations,
as a gold standard of any nation’s value, as a powerful “Plutarchian” example
for all of us to look up to.
No comments:
Post a Comment