The
title is a riddle of sorts. Daedalus was the mythical builder of the Labyrinth
of Minos on the island of Crete. Projecting the metaphor on the rest of this
section, its organization is rather convoluted and requires an Organization
and Structure entry, just like the Labyrinth of Minos required Ariadne’s
thread. So, here it is, designed purely for facilitating the reader’s walk
through the maze, sort of defeating its insurmountable complications. Hence, Anti-Daedalus.
We
are finally down to the standard sequence of pre-Socratic philosophers, and, not
surprisingly Thales, the first philosopher, opens the list. Breaking up
the chronological sequence (which we will have to be doing all the time), we
shall stay with the Milesian school, with Thales followed by Anaximander and
Anaximenes (as is customarily done, and there is no need for us to compound the
complications by breaking up our triad of Miletus). At this point we go back to
Thales’s time with Epimenides, and Pherecydes. Next, we are to find the
Pythagorean cluster stretching over a couple of centuries with Pythagoras,
Alcmaeon, Philolaus, Xenophiles, and Archytas. Xenophanes comes next by himself
(I am not counting him as an Eleatic, which is customary in standard
philosophical classifications), next followed by Heraclitus and his pupil
Cratylus, which ought not to diminish Heraclitus’s uniqueness. Next come the
Eleatics, headed by Parmenides, and followed by Zeno of Elea and Melissus.
Now
is the turn of Empedocles, by himself; next comes Anaxagoras and his pupil
Archelaus. The Atomists, that is, Leucippus and Democritus, are followed by
Diogenes of Apollonia, and then by a long succession of sophists, namely, by
Protagoras, Gorgias, Prodicus, Hippias, Thrasymachus, Callicles, and Antiphon.
(The standard list of the sophists usually includes Cratylus, who is already featured as a Heraclitus follower in an
earlier sequence, plus a certain Lycophron,
a potentially interesting, but too obscure a character, quoted by Aristotle in
his Politics 1280b10, as saying that “Law is only a convention, a surety to another of
justice.” I am sure that this quote is important enough by
itself to be discussed in one of the entries on the meaning of law, but it alone does not warrant a
special entry on Lycophron.)
The
section closes with what I call Socrates the Pre-Socratic, which is a
fancy way to say Socrates outside his portrayal by Plato, where the latter
occasionally ascribes his own ideas to his teacher, which, of course, belong in
our next section The Magnificent Shadows.
This
concludes our guide to the rest of PreSocratica Sempervirens, and, with
it, the present Anti-Daedalus entry.
No comments:
Post a Comment