Summarizing
the greatest achievement of the Milesian Triad, all three of them,
Thales, Anaximander, and Anaximenes were monists, that is, proponents of e
uno plures (paraphrasing the familiar American phrase e pluribus unum in
reverse). In several places elsewhere, I have been extolling the genius of
Greek monism, directly connected in the philosophical consciousness with an
espousal of monotheism, despite its seeming conflict with the preponderant
polytheistic religion of Ancient Greece. It is therefore a significant personal
accomplishment of each of the three that they have been such outspoken
champions of monism, and it is to their individual credits, each one of them,
regardless of their comparative value.
It
is also to their credit that each of them was an original thinker. Thales
apparently paved the way for all of them. Anaximander was not intimidated by
the towering genius of his older contemporary and probably his teacher, but
came up with an original system of his own. Anaximenes rejected his older
contemporary and probably his teacher, and substantially returned to Thales,
but he also rejected Thales’s specifics and came up with specifics of his own.
All three of them deserve much credit for treading their own unique paths.
Academic
profiles of the Milesians represent Thales and Anaximenes as physical
monists, because of their respective choices of water and air,
specific substances, as the original sources of everything.
Apparently, Anaximander’s boundless does not qualify as a specific
substance, although I categorically refuse to see it as something abstract. For
me, in so far as the significance of the boundless is concerned,
Thales’s water is clearly “boundless,” as earth itself floats on water, and,
apparently, water has no end. Anaximenes’ air, too, is boundless by his own
admission (“Air is the nearest to an immaterial
thing; for since we are generated in the flow of air, it is necessary that it
should be infinite and abundant, because it is never exhausted.”).
So, if these two “specific” substances are both infinite and inexhaustible, what
makes them so different in their physical principle from Anaximander’s unnamed
substance, which, I believe, can be treated exactly as the algebraic x, the
latter as we know, can stand for pretty much anything specific except
for being concrete in its identification. That’s why Anaximander said
that his boundless was nothing in particular. I hope that my good
analogy with the algebraic x clears up this issue enough, so that the reader
has by now figured out my point, and any further explanation on my part should
be either pointless or a waste of time.
With
this in mind, I find a curious misconception of the idea of the boundless in
Professor W T. Jones’s A History of Western Philosophy (New
York, Harcourt, Brace and Company, 1952). Not that I am using this
particular work as an authority on the subject, but Professor Jones was an established
academic and author of an important academic work, for which good reason his
apparent misconception deserves to be pointed out, and analyzed.
Here
is the paragraph titled Criticism of Anaximander (on page 36 of his History):
Anaximenes actually had good grounds for rejecting Anaximander’s
boundless. Consider: the boundless is an indefinite: it is everything, but
nothing in particular. But what sort of thing is something that is
nothing-in-particular? It has temperature, but no particular temperature; it
has color, but no particular color; and so on for all other specific qualities.
We have seen why Anaximander thought he had to say that boundless is nothing in
particular: if it is a particular thing it is impossible to understand how it
becomes its opposite. But we now see that this solution is itself open to
criticism. When we examine it closely we see that the term boundless really conveys no meaning;
there is nothing corresponding to it in our experience. So, instead of solving
a problem, it merely hides the fact that a problem exists, the problem, that
is, of understanding how one can become many. Either the boundless is simply a
grab-bag collection of the specific stuffs (in which case, it is not really one
at all, and monism is abandoned), or it is an indefinite something, which,
being nothing in particular, is not anything at all.
Much
of this criticism is already rebuffed by my algebraic x analogy: Dr.
Jones asks us, What sort of thing is something, which is
nothing-in-particular?, and answers it this way: Being nothing in
particular, is not anything at all. The secret of x is of course that it
cannot be pinpointed as one of the particulars, but being able to be any one of
them, it cannot possibly be nothing at all.
My
next objection to Dr. Jones’s analysis is that according to him the word boundless
conveys no meaning because there is nothing corresponding to it in our
experience. I wish he could be reminded that induction, which he has in
mind, is not the only game in town, but there is also deduction, which
does not depend on experience, and then, of course, there is such a thing as intuition…
Returning
to our Milesian triad proper, the final thing to discuss is whether all three
of them were mystics in the Nietzschean sense. Whereas it is fairly obvious
with Thales and Anaximander, the case is not quite clear with Anaximenes, as I
cannot quite figure out the thinking underlying his claim that the soul is
like air in its nature. Taken literally, this demystifies the soul, but
there is no ground to transfer the mystique of the soul onto his conception of
air. Other instances of his reasoning are even less conclusive in this regard,
and one may suspect that Nietzsche’s total omission of Anaximenes from the list
of his pre-Socratics throughout all his works may be an indication that he
failed to uncover a fellow mystic in him as well. But in my own appreciation
for Anaximenes I find undoubted respect for this great man, and I am willing to
extend to him the broadest benefit of the doubt, meaning that since I haven’t
found anything in him which denies him the mantle of a philosopher mystic, he
has surely earned it honoris et antiquitatis causa.
Can you tell me why it is obvious that Thales is a mystic? I would like to understand the evidence for that claim. Thanks.
ReplyDeletePerhaps you should read more of my Thales entries, such as Full of Gods, for instance.
ReplyDeleteAnyway, Thales's signature dictum "All things are full of gods" is a thoroughly mystical phrase, and if you disagree, this reveals our basic disagreement on the definition of "mystical."