Aristotle’s
Politica can be reduced to a single meaningful sentence: It’s good to be
rich and to have slaves, then you can be noble, good, and big-souled.
But
should we write more than one sentence about it, we ought to start with the
famous one-liner: “Man is by nature a political
animal,” and move on from there. The transition from ethics to politics
has occurred already, as we may rest assured that in the absence of perfect
contemplation, the political good becomes its worthy substitute.
The following paragraph is a
summary of Aristotle’s positive political theory by Bertrand Russell.
(The red font indicates my textual comments.) I call it “positive” in the sense that it can be
easily mistaken for such if separated from its negative component, which
shows us that in Aristotle’s State the notion of citizenship is by no means
enlightened.
Aristotle’s Politics begins by pointing out the importance
of the State: it is the highest kind of community, and aims at the highest
good. In order of time family comes first, built on the two fundamental
relations of man and woman, master and slave, both of which are natural. (Here is already the kernel of the ‘negative’
part of the theory, remaining ‘inactive’ only by this far remaining
unexplained) Several families
combined make a village; several villages, a State, provided the combination is
large enough to be self-sufficing. The State, though later in time than the family,
is prior to it and even to the individual; for “what each thing is when fully developed we call its
nature,” and human
society, fully developed, is a State,-- and the whole is prior to the part. The
conception involved here is that of organism: a hand, when the body is
destroyed, is no longer a hand. The implication is that a hand is to be defined
by its purpose--that of grasping--which it can only perform when joined to a
living body. (The parallel to
Hobbes is striking. Apparently with all his “anti-Aristotelity,” our
Hobbes finds nothing wrong in borrowing the great Greek’s imagery and logic.) In like manner an individual cannot
fulfill his purpose, unless he is part of a State. He who founded the State,
Aristotle says, was the greatest of benefactors; for, without law, man
is the worst of animals (and
under the law, Aristotle says, man is the best of animals), and law depends, for its existence, on
the State. The State is not a mere society for exchange and the prevention of
crime: “The end of the State
is the good life; the State is a union of families and villages in a perfect
and self-sufficing life, by which we mean a happy and honorable life. A
political society exist for the sake of noble actions, not of mere
companionship.”
Despite
all its visible shortcomings and apparent naïvetés, Aristotle’s political
theory is an important and thought-provoking probe into the nature of Hobbes’s Leviathan
(if I am permitted this awful anachronism), particularly fascinating
considering the fact that Hobbes’s earth-shaking masterpiece written two
thousand years later is in large measure a mere restatement of its glorious
distant predecessor. It is therefore right to say that Plato’s Politeia and
Aristotle’s Politica are the first two giant milestones of political
science, and, as such, no matter how many shortcomings these two works may
have, their world-historical philosophical worth can by no means be overrated.
It
is entirely logical for us to talk in one breath about Plato’s Politeia and
Aristotle’s Politica, because they ought to be contrasted in their
differences, which may not be as obvious to us (except for Politeia’s utopian
nature and Politica’s practicality) without taking note of Aristotle’s
criticism of Plato, which puts them in sharp focus. To use modern language
here, Plato comes out as a communist, whereas Aristotle is a staunch anti-communist,
almost a social-capitalist. Unlike Plato, Aristotle supports private
property, separateness and privacy of each family, limited involvement of the
State in family matters, etc. He believes rather in the voluntary charity
practice than in an obligatory sharing of wealth. This contrast is particularly
significant to me, as I have insisted throughout the relevant sections of this
book on the legitimacy of both of these social structures:
totalitarianism-socialism-communism à la Plato, and proto-capitalist mentality,
as represented by Aristotle.
But
it would be a big error to call Aristotle a pro-capitalist in the modern
sense of the word. His theory of trade is as anti-capitalist as they come. Take
this passage, for instance:
There are two sorts of wealth-getting, as I have said; one is a
part of household management, the other is retail trade: the former necessary
and honorable, while that which consists in exchange is justly censured; for,
it is unnatural, and it is a mode, by which men gain from one another. The most
hated sort, and with the greatest reason, is usury, which makes a gain out of
money itself, and not from the natural object of it. For, money was intended to
be used in exchange, but not to increase at interest… Of all modes of getting
wealth this is the most unnatural. (Politics: Book One; Part X-- 1257-1258.)
Why
do I say, then, that, as opposed to Plato, Aristotle is a proto-capitalist?
There is a peculiar reason that I shall seek to develop in the future, which,
in its present crude form, can be summarized like this:
I
am by no means talking about the economic principles of modern capitalism,
which are, indeed, founded on trade, money, and such. (Although certain ugly
excesses of financial capitalism, which can be described as usury
running amok, are, arguably, a perversion of healthy capitalism, plunging
society into the mire of unregulated greed and selfish antisocial
profiteering.) What I am talking about, is a special mental attitude directly
opposed to totalitarian collectivism, namely, individualism, which has evolved
throughout history in the economic circumstances of modern capitalism. It is
this anti-communistic, individualistic attitude, I find in Aristotle, which I
am calling, rather paradoxically, I admit, his proto-capitalistic disposition.
And
now, having said this, let us quickly consider the utterly negative side of
Aristotle’s political theory. I am particularly opposed to his rationalization
of the concept of slavery, as in the following excerpt:
We may infer that after the birth of animals, plants exist for
their sake, and that the other animals exist for the sake of man, the tame, for
use and food, the wild-- if not all, at least, the greater part of them-- for
food and for the provision of clothing and of various instruments. Now, if
nature makes nothing incomplete and nothing in vain, the inference must be that
she has made all animals for the sake of man. And thus, in one point of view,
the art of war is a natural art of acquisition, for the art of acquisition
includes hunting, an art which we ought to practice against wild beasts and
against men who, though intended by nature to be governed, will not submit; for
war of such a kind is naturally just. (Politics: Book One; Part VIII-- 1256.)
I
understand that in this excerpt Aristotle merely rationalizes the practice of
slave ownership by his fellow Greeks. (As I have stated his political
philosophy at the beginning of this entry, It’s good to be rich and to have
slaves, then you can be noble, good, and big-souled. Without his rationalization
and necessitation of slavery, the whole edifice of his political theory falls
apart. Therefore I have suggested that when the fatal flaw of his philosophical
necessitation of slavery had crumbled, his negative view of trade, and other
such natural principles of healthy capitalism, became the obvious casualties,
but his overall individualistic social attitude was transformed into the
capitalistic attitude, hence I have called Aristotle’s social attitude
“proto-capitalistic.”) I wonder how he would have adhered to this untenable
position when the tables were turned, and the Greeks became the slaves of the
Romans? But as for the ridiculous downside of his political theory, I think
that enough disparagement has been given to it already, as nothing that could
be added can top the philosophical absurdity of his treatment of the
institution of slavery, where the great Aristotle had willingly become a mere
political propagandist and happily for him did not live long enough for the
chicken to come home to roost.
No comments:
Post a Comment