Wednesday, May 21, 2014

CHRIST’S COMPETITOR IN ST. JEROME’S DREAM


It may well be that the title of this entry will eventually be replaced by something more appropriate, but for the moment I find it irresistible. I am talking about the person of Marcus Tullius Cicero (106-43 BC.), one of the most fascinating, famous and momentous people in history. Everybody (which includes myself) who has ever studied Latin, academically or otherwise, knows the name of Cicero, and has read plenty of him in the original, because without him Latin textbooks would have been half their normal size.

Cicero’s influence on his and subsequent generations has been immense, as, through his Latin translations and comments, the Western non-Greek world originally learned the names of Plato, Euclid, the Stoics, and others. He was accepted as a righteous pagan by the Christian Church, and all eminent Christian thinkers and theologians were known to have read Cicero with great appreciation. The title of this entry reflects the story of St. Jerome’s unusual experience with the great Roman, interestingly related in one of his letters. In this letter to his own Christian convert Eustochium he writes about his difficult ascetic experience. Having cut off his ties to family and friends, “and, harder still, from the dainty food which I had been accustomed to,” he still could not bear to resist his last temptation: the library of books, which he treasured. Departing for the desert, where he was going to fast for Christ, he took certain books with him. “And so, miserable man that I was, I would fast only that I might afterwards read Cicero.” Apparently, St. Jerome’s biggest problem was not reading Cicero, but preferring him to the prophets of the Bible, as one night, in a feverish dream, he was encountered by Christ at the Last Judgment, who challenged his claim of being a Christian: “Though liest, thou art a follower of Cicero and not of Christ.” Needless to say that after this experience, St. Jerome considerably moderated his zeal for Cicero and other Latin classics, but, rather surprisingly, he would never burn their books or drop them for good.

By no means surprisingly, a very similar experience is recorded by St. Augustine in his Confessions. Note that he uses the name of Tully (as in Marcus Tullius), as well as Cicero, in his references to him.

“I studied books of eloquence, wherein I was eager to be eminent from a damnable and inflated purpose, even a delight in human vanity. In the course of study, I lighted upon a book of Cicero, whose language, though not his heart, almost all admire. This book of his contains an exhortation to philosophy, and it is called Hortensius. This book, in truth, changed my affections and turned my prayers to Thyself, O Lord, and made me have other hopes and desires. Worthless suddenly became every vain hope to me; and, with an incredible warmth of heart, I yearned for an immortality of wisdom,(1) and began now to arise (2) that I might return to Thee. Not to improve my language did I have recourse to that book; nor did it persuade me by its style, but its matter.” Like St. Jerome, Augustine compares Cicero to the Bible, only to find the Bible wanting. “I resolved, therefore, to direct my mind to the Holy Scriptures, that I might see what they were. And behold, I perceive something not comprehended by the proud, not disclosed to children, but lowly as you approach, sublime as you advance, and veiled in mysteries; and I was not of the number of those who could enter into it, or bend my neck to follow its steps. For not as now did I feel when I tuned towards those Scriptures, but they appeared to me to be unworthy, compared with the dignity of Tully.”

Our next question addresses Cicero proper, rather than through his countless readers:

Was Cicero a philosopher? (This could be an alternative title for this entry!)

In my view he can be called a philosopher no less than Marcus Aurelius was one, and with infinitely more justification than the whole class of professional philosophers call themselves, who are philosophers mostly by college education and by choosing to write philosophical comments on other people’s ideas. Perhaps, it is possible to call him a philosophical dilettante, because philosophy was not his main occupation, and he is neither a founder nor a follower of any particular school, although of them all, he is the closest to Stoicism. Throughout his life, he had a great love for philosophy. Superbly educated in Greek language and culture, he was fond of translating Greek philosophical works into Latin, and, finding the Latin language wanting in many abstract terms existing in Greek, he worked on enriching his native language by coining a parallel set of terms in Latin. This last accomplishment of his is, for some reason, the least known to non-linguists but, theoretically, it elevates him to a level of excellence that very few great men in history can boast of.

Having studied Roman law with greatest distinction, Cicero is also famous for elaborating a philosophy of jurisprudence, having articulated an abstract conceptualization of rights based on ancient law and custom. His legal background determined his later philosophical emphasis on public, rather than private good. For this reason he criticizes Epicureanism but praises the Stoics, in his philosophical opus De Finibus, where he advances the Stoic view that “the greatest good consists in applying to the conduct of life a knowledge of the workings of natural causes, choosing what is according to nature and rejecting what is contrary to it; in other words, the greatest good is to live in agreement and in harmony with nature.”

In 87 BC he became a student of Philo of Larissa, the head of Plato’s Academy in Athens, who had arrived in Rome at the time. Cicero declared his love for Plato, but nevertheless showed intellectual independence, by rejecting Plato’s key doctrine of Ideas. He continued his studies of philosophy and traveled to Athens to familiarize himself with different schools of thought, plus to learn rhetorical skills for his public office.

As I said earlier, Cicero being a good Roman citizen, his conception of virtue centered on public virtue. In his work De Officiis, written for the instruction of his son Marcus, he writes:

No phase of life, whether public or private, whether in business or in the home, whether one is working on what concerns oneself alone or dealing with another, can be without its own moral duty. On the discharge of such duties depends all which is morally right, and on their neglect all that is morally wrong in life. By the same token, the concept of justice centers on the conservation of organized society, with rendering to each his due, and with faithful discharge of obligations assumed. The first office of justice is to keep each man from doing harm to another, unless provoked by a wrong; and the next is to lead men to use common possessions for their common interests, and private property for their own.

Very appropriately for a philosopher and a good man (if I am allowed to speak this shocking truth), Cicero ended his life as a martyr. Remembering him, the Emperor Augustus Caesar, according to Plutarch, called him “A learned man who loved his country.” Perhaps, for a Roman, this was not an understatement, but the highest compliment…

No comments:

Post a Comment