Tuesday, May 27, 2014

THE LAST ROSE OF THE GREEK SUMMER


The title alludes to the classic 1805 poem by the Irish poet Thomas Moore The Last Rose of Summer, that became an exceptionally popular song, spawning multiple important musical adaptations. Its relevance to my entry on Plotinus is in its metaphorical use.

It is hard to be unequivocal about our next subject of interest, namely, Plotinus (204-270) who is named in all histories of philosophy as an eminent Neo-Platonist. On the one hand, being called a Platonist does not confer on one a badge of originality, suggesting a strong derivative quality. Besides, he might be described as a poor man’s Plato, in the sense that one can learn only so much of Plato from reading Plotinus. He is a lover of Plato, who does not do his love justice by concentrating only on several aspects of Plato’s theories, while completely ignoring the rest. On the same side of the pro/contra argument is the fact that Nietzsche, a great connoisseur of ancient Greek philosophy, does not mention him by name even once, anywhere I looked.

But on the other side of the argument is the earlier mentioned fact that no history of philosophy can forgo him, and our friend Bertrand Russell (who is a formidable authority in philosophy and on philosophers) is quite generous to Plotinus, allotting him a lengthy fourteen-page Plotinus chapter, the very last chapter of the First Book of his History of Western Philosophy (Ancient Philosophy), and calling him “the last of the great philosophers of antiquity,” and rather than stressing his derivative quality, as a mere follower of Plato, emphasizes his originality by calling him “the founder of Neo-Platonism.

With regard to the very last point, before we talk further about Plotinus himself, we may find it interesting to ascertain that Neo-Platonism can indeed be considered as an original school of philosophy, rather than a wholly derivative spin-off of Plato’s Platonism. W. T. Jones gives his explanation why Neo-Platonism is so important by raising two key points. One, that its particular emphasis on religiosity, far more pronounced than in Plato, reflected the specific mood of the times (Plotinus’ Third Century AD). The other, that, had it not been for Plotinus and his new school of Neo-Platonic thinking, Plato’s virtual defeat by the philosophy of Aristotle would have been complete. While attempting to solve the technical philosophical problems on which Platonism broke, and to which Aristotle had provided at best only a partial answer, Neo-Platonism developed a philosophy of religion that was to become a major influence on the future course of Western thought. Indeed, Neo-Platonism proved to be one of the chief modes of Plato’s endurance.

The main difference-- and hence the new philosophy’s originality-- between Platonism and Neo-Platonism was that the former was focused on ethics, while the latter was focused on religion. Plato’s anti-rationalism was embraced, but his belief in the possibility of acquiring real knowledge rationally was ignored, not like the Skeptics ignored it, to prove their Ignoramus et Ignorabimus, but in order to insist that real knowledge could only be acquired irrationally through religious mysticism and revelation. Thus, Neo-Platonism was a deliberate effort to adapt Plato, that is, to enlist him into the service of a new philosophy, which sprang out of a non-Platonic pool, but so much liked what Plato had to say, when he was not in contradiction with its own doctrinal tenets, that it effectively appropriated Plato’s name and clout, not unlike Fritz Kreisler using hallowed names in classical music to promote his own compositions, written in the old style, but not quite the same…

The Neo-Platonic school of thinking was therefore a brand new line of thinking, or perhaps, a philosophical agenda, which pushed itself so vigorously, and found for itself such fertile soil in the new age, that it found it possible to alter classical Platonism in its new image so that the tables were turned and on the surface it may even seem that Plato had become a Plotinus derivative!

A few words now about Plotinus proper. He was by no means a Christian thinker (Christianity at that time was still under persecution), otherwise we would not have called him the last of the Greeks. But he had an enormous influence on Christianity, particularly on Eastern orthodox Christianity, which relies on him far more than Western Catholicism (which has received its “Aristotelian component” not via Plotinus, but via Thomas Aquinas, who, curiously, had less of an influence on the Eastern Branch of Christianity!).

Someone familiar with Jewish Kabbalah would instantly recognize a strong connection between Plotinus’s theory of The One (Ein Sof) and of the Emanations from the unknowable and perfect into less perfect and more knowable and the Kabbalistic theories of the same. It must be borne in mind, however, that Plotinus had come before any Kabbalah existed, and thus there has been no influence of Jewish thinkers on the last Greek, but exactly the other way round. It was the Kabbalah that developed these mystical theological and philosophical conceptions in the wake of Plotinus’s metaphysical explorations!

And finally, Plotinus was perhaps at his least Greek and at his most Christian-like in his attitude toward the physical body. According to his Neo-Platonic disciple Porphyry he hated his body and resolutely refused to discuss the circumstances of his early physical life. (He was born in Egypt but everything else about him or his family is completely obscure, including the year of his birth, which is counted back with approximation from the known date of his death.) He insisted that the philosophical objective of human existence was to ignore the minutia of everything pertaining to this world, concentrating instead on the contemplation of the goodness and beauty embodied by The One. Not that The One could suddenly become accessible, through such contemplation, but whatever coming to us from the other world via the emanations reached in these contemplations constituted the highest aim of philosophy and of human existence as such.
…My friend Nietzsche would surely make an extra-sour grimace here… But philosophical tastes vary and differ, and, whether he liked it or not, we are all the richer for it!
This is the end of the Graeco-Roman, “pagan” subsection, and next we shall continue with early Christian philosophy, as opposed to theology, and our first name on this list is not Saint Augustine, as expected, but … Origen.

No comments:

Post a Comment