With
regard to Aristotle’s logic, Bertrand Russell makes an insightful comment,
which boils down to why exactly we often confess to hating Aristotle, while
admiring most of his peers, but also many philosophers of far lesser statures.
The answer is that those philosophers whom we so admire are usually mere
historical relics to us, long out of contention for the minds of modernity,
whereas Aristotle and his logic are still very much in play, and still present
a challenge to our modern thinking. I am tempted to compare this situation to
the modern attitude toward the great Nietzsche, who has as many ardent fans as
ferocious enemies, both of them on account of his super-active status in the
actuality of modern thinking, and in large measure because of his alleged
intellectual and spiritual ties to the philosophy of the Third Reich.
There
is a difference, however. Nietzsche is a modern thinker, in many ways
ahead of the curve, while the classical logic of Aristotle is no longer the
cutting edge, but its awesome perennial prestige has been used to promote a
certain backwardness of thinking, and has thus become a victim by association.
It
is therefore imperative to repeat that, no matter what, Aristotle’s logic remains
a titanic achievement of the human mind, one of the largest milestones in the
history of human civilization, and any excessive criticism of him on
account of the amazing longevity of his brainchild is an example of the unfair
practice of guilt by association. In this regard, Russell’s argument is of special
interest, when he says this:
"Aristotle’s logical writings show great ability and would have been
useful to mankind, if they had appeared at a time when intellectual originality
was still active. But, unfortunately, they appeared at the very end of the
creative period of Greek thought, and, therefore, came to be accepted as
authoritative. By the time that logical originality revived, a reign of two
thousand years had made Aristotle very difficult to dethrone, and throughout
modern times, practically every advance in science, logic, or philosophy, has
had to be made in the teeth of the opposition from Aristotle’s disciples."
As
for his evaluation of Aristotle’s logic for modern times, Russell is uncommonly
harsh in his judgment: "I conclude that the Aristotelian
doctrines, with which we have been concerned in this chapter, [on logic] are wholly false,
with the exception of the formal theory of the syllogism which is… unimportant. Any person in
the present day who wishes to learn logic will be wasting time reading
Aristotle or any of his disciples."
Even
if this is partly true, nevertheless, a few elements of Aristotle’s logic need
to be presented here.
The
cornerstone concept of Aristotelian logic is the syllogism, which is a
three-part argument, consisting of a major premise, a minor premise, and the
conclusion, or, in his own words, “a discourse, in
which, certain things being stated, something different from these things
follows of necessity from their being so.”
The
most famous and original in the chronological sense syllogism is All men are mortal (major
premise); Socrates is a man (minor premise); therefore Socrates is
mortal (conclusion). All other types of syllogism can be reduced to
this one. In developing his logic, Aristotle believed that all deductive
reasoning is such that it can be reduced to the syllogism. The only task
remained to set every argument in syllogistic form. (This optimistic belief in
the syllogism managed to mislead all philosophers until Kant, as to the nature
of mathematical reasoning. Kant understood that mathematics was not
syllogistic, but concluded that it had to be governed by extra-logical principles,
which in itself was a surrender of sorts to Aristotle’s authority.) As a matter
of fact, not only was the syllogism inessential to deductive reasoning, the
latter itself was not the exclusive mode of reasoning. Aside from deduction,
there was also induction, and Aristotle recognized its importance, when he
raised the question of how we arrive at the first premises from which deduction
is supposed to start. Whereas the title of his work on the syllogistic logic
was The Prior Analytics, induction was discussed in The Posterior
Analytics. It is impossible, Aristotle admits, to go backwards through our
deduction incessantly. At some point in this regression, we must arrive at a
premise that cannot be deduced from a preceding syllogism, and, in this case,
we are dealing with an intuitive truth, which reveals itself to our intuitive
reason (nous), which is the mental faculty that knows without proof. Examples
of such truths are, according to Aristotle’s mistaken impression, the basic
axioms of geometry. Such self-evident truths, he believed, exist in every science…
Who
said that Aristotle’s logic was not at all interesting? From this exciting
discussion of” induction,” we now
know how Kant got himself mixed up with those dangerous chimeras, the aprioris!
No comments:
Post a Comment