Saturday, May 24, 2014

THE SLAVE WHO WOULD POSSESS AN EMPEROR’S SOUL


The Stoic philosopher Epictetus (his years of life have not been credibly established, but according to some sources, they could be 55-135 AD) is well known from two extant works, ironically, neither written by him. The Discourses and The Enchiridion were both written by his student Flavius Arrian, claiming to represent the master’s authentic sayings. He is also the single most important factor in the philosophical development of the Roman “Philosopher-Emperor Marcus Aurelius.

In a certain sense, we can use toward all Stoics the very unkind phrase to the effect that once you have read one, you have read them all. Indeed, where they are important, they are all very much alike, and where they are different, they are not all that important. Thus, philosophically speaking, there is no need to allot all of them more than a single entry, which though, as the reader must have noticed, is by no means the case here. The reason for such prominence of the Stoics lies therefore in their extra-philosophical, that is, in their historical and cultural value, and this point must also be clearly understood.

Among the names appearing in this section, many are new, but some are familiar from previous, thematic sections. Our present subject Epictetus belongs to the diversified group. We’ve met him already in my entry Definitions, Definitions, Definitions!--- (Talking about definitions, and our uncritical use of poorly, if at all defined terminology, which turns us into slaves of the powers that are shoving their calculated usage down our throat, here is another precious excavation, from Epictetus’s Enchiridion: First learn the meaning of what you say, and then speak.” Bravo, Epictete!)

And then, from my entry Evil And The Nature Of Things.--- (Epictetus makes short shrift of the question of evil. He says, As a mark is not set up for the purpose of missing it, so neither does the nature of evil exist in the universe.Simplicius has a lengthy and curious discourse on this text of Epictetus, both amusing and very instructive: Evil is not part of the nature of things,he argues.If there were a principle of evil in the constitution of things, evil would no longer be evil, but evil would be good.

Curiously, in one particularly important aspect, Epictetus sounds very much like a Pythagorean.--- Quoting Bertrand Russell on this, “On earth, says Epictetus, we are prisoners, and in an earthly body. According to Marcus Aurelius, he used to say ‘Thou art a little soul bearing about a corpse.’ Zeus could not make body free, but he gave us a portion of his divinity…” In another instance, now quoting from the Enchiridion, he sounds uncannily like a consummate Christian in the true Pauline mold: If you desire to be good, begin by believing that you are wicked. W. T. Jones notes that “there was a Christian community in his birthplace, and it has been assumed that Christianity exercised an influence on his thought.” He quickly adds though, that “the parallelism between some of Epictetus’ teachings and those of the Christians may however be the result of the contemporary climate of opinion, to which all thinking men,--- Christians and non-Christians alike,-- contributed and from which, in turn, they drew.” I am however unsure that the affinity of the phrase I quoted earlier can be explained away without acknowledging its close Christian ties.

Nietzsche has a few references to Epictetus, in one place (in Menschliches) calling him “a great moralist.” (But one must admit to himself that our age is poor in great moralists, that Pascal, Epictetus, Seneca, and Plutarch are now read but little.) In Morgenröte, he comments on Stoical selfishness, using Epictetus yet again as his example: The great men of antique morality, Epictetus for instance, knew nothing of the now normal glorification of thinking of others, of living for others; in the light of our moral fashion they would have to be called downright immoral, for they strove with all their might for their ego and against feeling with others (that is to say with the sufferings and moral frailties of others). Perhaps they would reply to us: “If you are so boring or ugly an object to yourself, by all means think of others more than of yourself! It is right you should!” (For the record, while Nietzsche mentions Epictetus in several other places, there is no mention of Marcus Aurelius anywhere in his writings, as far as I remember, which is Nietzsche’s way of saying that the Emperor’s philosophy is utterly derivative.)
 
Curiously, Nietzsche is silent on the ‘Christian’ side of Epictetus’ teachings, apparently finding it wiser to take on the real thing, than a proxy. But it is his affinity with the Christian spirit of the ages to come, which makes Epictetus particularly interesting to us. As Dr. W. T. Jones puts it, the whole of Epictetus’ teaching could be summed up, he said, in two words: bear and forbear. “If a man will only have these two words at heart, and heed them carefully, by ruling and watching over himself, he would for the most part fall into no sin, and his life will be tranquil and serene.”

I guess this last part should suit only the optimistic Christian hermit. Those who are bent on the sinfulness of human nature cannot reconcile themselves to the idea of tranquil and serene life in this world.
(The complementary entry on Marcus Aurelius, under the title Thoughts On Thoughts, follows next.)

No comments:

Post a Comment