Timon of Phlius (320-235 BC) was a follower of Pyrrho the
Skeptic, and he flourished long after Timon of Athens, who had lived during the
Peloponnesian War, in the fifth century BC, and was mentioned both by Plutarch
and Lucian as a separate historical figure. It is mainly the older Timon the
misanthrope, who was made the central character of Shakespeare’s play Timon
of Athens, although certain parts of Shakespeare’s hero’s persona have been
casually appropriated from the Skeptic.
This little known, and even less cared about, case of
occasionally confused identity, adds a certain spice to my choice of the
subject of this entry, who is, of course, the Skeptic. Ironically, having been
born in Phlius, and lived for some time in Elis, he eventually moved to Athens,
where he died in very old age, making him, to some extent, and to promote further
confusion, another Timon of Athens.
Unlike
Stoicism, Greek Skepticism is a relatively minor philosophical event, and, unlike
Diogenes of Sinope and Epicurus, the founders of Skepticism Pyrrho and Timon
are rather minor historical figures. There are a few nuances, however,
justifying the writing of this short entry, one of them admittedly
superficial,--- referring to the confusion between my subject and Shakespeare’s
Timon of Athens, which, by itself, would have been demonstrably
insufficient.
Among
other nuances is the famous catchphrase, always rendered in Latin as Ignoramus
et Ignorabimus. It catches the essence of philosophical skepticism, and,
like a single mathematical hypothesis at the basis of a comprehensive theory,
allows everything skeptical that has ever been uttered, to be logically
and very easily reduced to it.
Unlike
the somewhat skeptical Sophists, who had expressed their utter mistrust for
sensory perception, but preferred to stop there, the Skeptics, starting with
their founding father Pyrrho, pushed Skepticism beyond that limit, expressing
complete mistrust for ethical and logical rules and norms of behavior. There
was not a shred of evidence to put one norm above another, thus the guiding
principle of morality was adhering to the customs of the country wherever one
happened to reside at that particular time. Moving from one place to another,
obligated the individual to reshape his behavior, sometimes quite radically, in
order to conform to the new surroundings.
Another
logical consequence of Skepticism, which was promoted by the Skeptics and was
sure to generate some public appeal, was that one should never worry about the
future, which was totally unpredictable, but live in the present, enjoying it
as much as one could, while the moment lasted. This of course smacks of too
much pandering to the lower affects, and too little philosophy, a dirty trick
that effectively handicapped the competition.
But
there was also an interesting philosophical reasoning, apparently belonging to Timon,
which denied the possibility of finding general principles for all deductive
doctrines. This impossible to refute argument hit Aristotle’s doctrine of “aprioris”
straight in the face, and was also one that the great old Kant was himself
never able to overcome, but, rather disingenuously, tried to get around. This
intellectual challenge is still very relevant in modern
philosophical-scientific thinking, and, for being the first to bring it up, Timon
objectively deserves to be awarded his own entry.
In
summary of all of the above, neither Skepticism nor the Skeptics are
interesting enough to devote much time to their study, but certain things about
them surely merit our very brief attention.
No comments:
Post a Comment