It is a sad memory for another
Irishman on our list, John Duns Scotus (1266-1308), whose name Duns was turned
into the unflattering epithet “dunce” after King Henry the
Eighth’s repudiation of the Pope and of all Catholicism with that.
Duns Scotus was a Franciscan
friar, one of the three great Franciscan philosophers, counting Roger Bacon and
William Occam (you will find him in my next entry, to be posted tomorrow),
besides him. By contrast, Albertus Magnus and Thomas Aquinas were Dominicans.
There existed a certain enmity between these two orders: the Dominicans were
considered more orthodox, while the Franciscans, refusing to accept their authority,
were seen as straying off the conventional course. This does not mean that the
Franciscans were perched on the verge of heresy. Curiously enough, their bitter
rivalry with the Dominicans caused Pope Sixtus IV, in the fifteenth century, to
write a constitution threatening both sides with excommunication should they
keep accusing each other of heresy. The case in point was the doctrine of the Immaculate
Conception, originally formulated in the eleventh century, but immediately
rejected by Church authorities, including Doctor Angelicus-- St. Thomas
himself. This doctrine was, however, brought back to prominence by none other
than Duns Scotus, and by virtue of his sharply refined argument was established
as an optional Church practice. (It was going to become an official dogma of
the Church only in 1854, precisely because of the stated Dominican opposition
to it.)
From all said above, it is clear
that Duns Scotus was poising himself against the authority of Aquinas. This was
possible by appealing to the authority of Augustine, which Duns was doing very
skillfully. Thus, in his philosophy, the effective ratio of Plato versus
Aristotle in the philosophical concoction of the Middle Ages Christian theology
was pushed back from Thomistic Aristotle back to Augustinian Plato.
But this was not all that
happened as a result of Duns’ efforts. Without actually trying to dislodge
Aquinas from his lofty position within the Catholic Church, Duns discovered
numerous chinks in his armor, and set on to correct those mistakes. His grudge
was against giving too much credit to reason and philosophy, thus leaving too
little room for revelation and supernatural illumination. It may be true that
Thomas Aquinas is vulnerable because of such obvious mistakes (after all, every
philosopher presenting a theory of his own is necessarily guilty of multiple errors,
which, after all said and done, completely undermine his construction and turn
his theory into a pathetic pile of junk), but at least what he was trying to do
was to reconcile these two apparent opposites: reason and revelation;
philosophy and theology standing behind them. By his too thorough an effort to
push philosophy out of theology, Duns Scotus antagonized philosophy at a time
when it had too little clout in its standing against the Church. With the
advent of the Renaissance, however, the tables were turned, and a triumphant
philosophy pushed back and trivialized theology among all educated minds. Was
it worth it, then, we may ask, to repair small parts, while losing the big
whole?
The name of Duns, now spelled as dunce,
became a nickname for a mentally challenged person, because of Duns
Scotus’s alleged obscurity and obtuseness. On the other hand, he is known as Doctor
Subtilis among the Catholics for his sharp thorough mind and a genius for
the subtleties of extremely difficult, specialized philosophical subject
matter. In many ways he epitomizes scholasticism at its peak. But among those
truly obscure, abstruse subjects, which have made him, and Catholic
Scholasticism as a whole, the butt of many irreverent jokes, there is at least
one subject, which is at the same time lively, instructive, and useful in the
modern philosophical discourse. It is the “principle of individuation,”
that is what determines non-identity of things, and in addressing this question
Duns Scotus particularly excelled. Here is how Bertrand Russell describes his
contribution:
“Duns
Scotus held that, since there is no difference between being and essence,
the principle of individuation must be form, not matter. This principle
was one of the important problems of the scholastic philosophy. In various
forms it has remained a problem to the present day. We may state the problems
as follows.
“Among
the properties of individual things, some are essential, others accidental. The
question now arises: given two individual things belonging to the same species,
do they always differ in essence, or is it possible for the essence to be
exactly the same in both? Saint Thomas holds the latter view on material
substances, the former on the immaterial ones. Duns Scotus holds that there are
always differences of essence between two different individual things.
The view of St. Thomas depends on the theory that pure matter consists of
undifferentiated parts, which are distinguished solely by difference of
position in space. Duns Scotus holds that if things are distinct, they must be
distinguished by some qualitative difference. This view is nearer to Platonism
than that of St. Thomas.”
Russell says further that in
modernizing this problem, as we get rid of the concept of substance altogether,
Scotus is more up to par than Aquinas, although the serious difficulty in
connection with space and time is still unresolved. In my view, it is possible
to overcomplicate the philosophical problem of individuation, to bring it even
to the point of absurdity, like Zeno Eleaticus has done with his logical
puzzles, but in view of the recent cloning experiments becoming a trend-setting
development, the principle of individuation ought to be posited in ethical
terms, rather than in any other non-ethical philosophical terms, and only the
position of Duns Scotus, which unequivocally separates even seemingly identical
entities, can sustain the principle of individuation through the cloning
controversy. It is essential to see two clones, or two identical twins as
distinct not only mentally or immaterially, as St. Thomas would allow it, but
as physically distinct as well, where only a categorical qualitative physical
distinction will do, thus awarding the whole argument to Duns Scotus.
No comments:
Post a Comment