…Having
thus established Erigena’s bona fides in more than one way, let us touch upon
his life and thought, as both are of great interest to the history of
philosophy, and also to me personally.
He
was born in Ireland between 810 and 815, but later emigrated to the Continent
in a wave of emigrations, caused by a series of barbarian Scandinavian
invasions that did nothing good for the cause of culture except for returning
it from the no longer wild west closer to its original home eastward. In
845 he was accepted at the court of Charles the Bald, whose own possessions
including Paris were being ravaged by the Normans.
Erigena’s
authority as a classical scholar with an invaluable knowledge of Greek had been
well established by the time he traveled to France. Getting into theological
trouble all the time, due to his independent mind and a highly unorthodox
preference for honest philosophy and reason over dogmatic theology and
religious revelation, he, however, was extremely lucky not to be branded a
heretic in his lifetime, thanks to his great scholarly reputation, and the
royal protection of his benefactor. Only well after his death would his
writings be condemned, and even burned as heretical, guaranteeing him a virtual
oblivion, but, luckily, not an everlasting one, as the fortuitous rediscovery
of his manuscripts in Oxford in 1681 brought him back to life and established
him ever since as a foremost thinker of all time. The end of his life is
clouded in total obscurity. Most sources give 877 as the year of his death,
without any ground, except for the fact that his royal benefactor died in that
year. There is a legend that after Charles the Bald died, he left for England,
where Alfred the Great bestowed more honors on the old man, for which (or,
perhaps, for something else) Erigena’s students at Oxford stabbed him to death
with their styli. This is, however, only a legend, and there is no factual or
circumstantial substantiation for it whatsoever.
Erigena’s
first theological work (which has been irrevocably destroyed, but its gist is
known) was devoted to the subject of the Eucharist, and it was instantly
controversial and potentially blasphemous. We know of the later disagreement
between the Roman Catholics and the Protestants, concerning transubstantiation
versus consubstantiation, both, however, entailing substantiation, that
is, the transformation of bread and water, in the course of the sacrament, into
the body and blood of Christ. Erigena dismissed this transformation out of
hand. His view, closely resembling that of modern Baptists, is that the
Eucharist is a purely symbolic rite, in which no substantiation ever takes
place. Erigena never suffered the consequences of his heresy, but its later
proponents such as, say, Berengar of Tours did. Most ironically, as part of his
forced penance Berengar was required to publicly burn… that selfsame Erigena’s
treatise!
In
his treatise On Divine Predestination Erigena defended free will
and couldn’t resist the daring challenge of defending philosophy and reason
against their ecclesiastical repudiation. He contended that philosophy is not
inferior, but sometimes even superior to revelation, in the sense that both
reason and revelation are bona fide sources of truth, and are not supposed to
come in conflict with each other, but if they should, this would not be the
reason’s fault, but there must have been something wrong with the revelation.
An amazing boldness in a very dangerous time for it!
His
attitude toward hell is no less heretical. For Erigena, hell is not a place,
but a condition for purification, and eventually, after such purification, all
God’s Creation, including the demons, was to join God in good harmony. Once
again, one must marvel how such liberties on his part did not bring Erigena
into some very serious harm, but this odd fact remains, that he thus went
through his whole life, ever ranting and raving, yet emerging unscathed at the
end.
Another
outstanding fact of Erigena’s intellectual accomplishments was his already mentioned
translation from Greek into Latin of the Neo-Platonic works of
Pseudo-Dionysius. (See the previous entry.) On having receiving the
translation, Pope St. Nicholas I the Great was offended only by the fact that
his permission for this translation had not been sought in the first place, but
he refrained from any negative comments on the controversial treatment of
theology in it, and he even expressed an admiration, based on the opinion of
his Greek scholars, for the superlative quality of Erigena’s translation and
exhibited scholarship.
Erigena’s
magnum opus, as I have already said, was his work De Divisione Naturae (Periphyseon),
where he divides the whole of nature into four classes: [1] what creates and
is not created (God); [2] what creates and is created (the Platonic ideas which
subsist in God); [3] what is created and does not create (all things in space
and time); and [4] what neither creates nor is created (God again, but this
time teleological rather than the first cause). Thus, everything comes from
God, and through Logos returns to Him. It is easy to see the connection
with Hegel’s Phenomenology of Spirit here, although the influence of the
one on the other can hardly be ascertained. Establishing such connections of
influence we may convincingly argue that Erigena has borrowed the first three
classes of being from Aristotle (whom he however criticizes, preferring Plato
to him), and the fourth class from Pseudo-Dionysius, who teaches the return of
all being into God.
Aside
from the four classes of being, there is also a realm of non-being, which
includes all physical things which do not belong to the intelligible world, but
also sin (!), which are not parts of the divine pattern. This teaching
is also greatly suspect, which means that any powerful ill-wisher could easily
accuse Erigena of a large number of heresies, but one of the reasons why this
had not happened must have been the mentioned Biblical authority of Dionysius,
which may, most of the time, have been Erigena’s powerful shield against such
trouble, and, most probably, his chief motivation for drafting Dionysius under
his banner, in the first place.
A
remarkable life, a remarkable personal luck, and a wonderful fortune for
posterity to have the knowledge of this man and his work restored to us,
proving that even the darkest ages of our cultural history have not been
altogether pitch dark.
No comments:
Post a Comment