Homo Scholasticus is my
jocular designation for St. Thomas Aquinas (1225-1274), finally, the sole subject
of this entry. Not that he was the only scholastic in the age of scholasticism,
of course, but he was by far the most important scholastic, the crowning
epitome of scholasticism as such, and also, unquestionably, one of the most authoritative
thinkers of all time.
***
Virtually every history of
philosophy places Thomas Aquinas among the preeminent philosophical figures of
all time. W. T. Jones gives him several chapters, on a par with Plato and
Aristotle. Bertrand Russell has a single chapter on him, but it is just as
lengthy as his chapters on Hobbes, Dèscartes, and Spinoza. By such standards I
might have put him in the Magnificent Shadows section, allotting him a
number of entries, but I am doing no such thing, and that for a very good
reason. While St. Thomas Aquinas has been undeniably one of the most
influential thinkers in history, he is hardly a major philosopher of an
interest comparable to the giants of Western philosophy.
The reasons for his extraordinary
authority are easy to see. Comparing his biography to the biographies of other
Christian thinkers, including the Saints of the Church, in the Catholic
Encyclopedia, we find that this one reads like a genuine hagiography,
putting him almost on a par with St. Paul the Apostle and the Saints of the
Bible’s New Testament. Already during his life, his virtually supernatural
prestige was growing with a certain promise of speedy canonization after his
death (which, indeed, followed after the shortest allowable wait of just
forty-nine years, in 1323. (For comparison, it took St. Augustine 873
postmortem years to reach the same status.) In 1368, Saint Thomas’s teaching
was endorsed by Pope Urban V as the infallible dogma of the Catholic Church.
(Pope Urban V: “The teaching of Blessed Thomas is
the true and Catholic doctrine.”) For comparison, no similar
endorsement has ever been given to any other Doctor of the Church. Ironically
it was Martin Luther who endorsed St. Augustine (but by no means as
powerfully), in his 1569 Tischreden: “Augustine
was the ablest and purest of all the doctors.” Needless to
say that by this denigration of Thomas and elevation of Augustine, Luther was
disparaging his enemy the Catholic Church, while building up for his supporters
a parallel Protestant authority,-- St. Augustine. {Luther’s elevation of Augustinian
theology has produced, among several unhappy effects, the Protestant belief,
lasting into the twenty-first century, but in a slightly modified form, in the
perdition of the “unbaptized” (that is, of all those who do not know Jesus),
which the Roman Catholic Church had long abandoned.}
Urban V’s sanction was repeated
and reinforced in 1879 by Pope Leo XIII, who pontificated, ex cathedra,
that in all Catholic educational institutions teaching philosophy, the
doctrines of St. Thomas Aquinas had to be taught as the only right ones.
With such an exceptional
imprimatur, no wonder that St. Thomas has long become, and remains, the most
important philosopher in history, in the eyes of the Roman Catholic Church’s 1.13
billion Faithful around the world. (For the sake of fairness, I must remind
the reader that the Catholic system of education has not suffered much as a
result of such imprimaturs. It is still one of the best in the world, beating
the American system of Multiple Choice into silly pulp, at that!)
Yet we can scarcely call St.
Thomas a first-rate philosopher for several reasons. On the one hand, he is too
closely conjoined to Aristotelian philosophy to amount to much on his own.
Then, rather than engaging in an open-minded philosophical inquiry, all he does
is he adapts his “findings” to a fixed set of pre-ordained conclusions. And
these conclusions are not even his own unique discoveries, but the official
ordinances of the ruling power, which is the Roman Catholic Church. Thus St.
Thomas shows himself, rather, as a clever promoter of the Church’s doctrine
than as an honest thinker with any claim to intellectual independence.
With all due respect, aside from
adapting Aristotle’s theories to the needs of the Church, his philosophy is
wholly reducible to the following homiletic poem of his composition:
Pange, lingua, gloriosi
Corporis mysterium,
Sanguinisque pretiosi,
Quem in mundi pretium
Fructus ventris generosi
Rex effudit gentium.
Wherever he finds himself capable
of supporting the Catholic dogma with Aristotle’s rational authority, he does
it very capably. Wherever, however, he finds this impossible, he immediately
appeals to the authority of revelation, where he does not have to prove
anything. This renders his job conveniently uncomplicated, and invariably
rewarding; but, to his credit, even those things that are demonstrably too easy
to do, he does them with an undeniable intellectual flair and with greatness.
Thus, some aspects of his saintly, demiurgic reputation are actually well deserved.
Generally speaking, I do not wish
to disparage St. Thomas’s legacy in any way by an unwanted impression of veiled
sarcasm. He was objectively a great man, and his enormous prominence within the
framework of Western civilization makes him, honoris causa, a figure of
unconditionally lofty stature. But his personal philosophical greatness is
incommensurate with his world-historical cultural significance, to the point
that I feel no compulsion or interest in analyzing the details of his
philosophy or of his theology, which stance of mine needs to be mentioned and
explained, which I hope I have done with sufficient clarity.
But before I am done with this
entry, I would like to bring the reader back to the concluding paragraphs of
the earlier entry on Saint Augustine (City Of God) and continue quoting
our old friend W. T. Jones, in his Conclusion to The Medieval Mind, which
is Part II of his History of Western Philosophy. This time, he is
comparing St. Thomas to St. Augustine:
"Although
Thomas, as compared with Augustine, was much more humane, most of us are a long
way from feeling at home with his thought. He certainly wanted to allow a
measure of significance to this world and its affairs, but most people will
feel that he failed to reconcile God’s infinity with man’s value. And what if
by some feat of logical synthesis, he succeeded? Even so, for both Thomas and
Augustine, man’s best and truest end still lies beyond this life; the world is
still a great teleological structure, which gets its meaning from where it is
going, rather than from what it is and does, and the final sanction for all
conduct, and the ultimate criterion for all knowledge is not the concurrence of
human reasons, but an authoritative text and a divine institution.
What
makes Augustine and Thomas, and all other medieval thinkers, so fundamentally
alike, despite their differences, is the sacramental outlook, which they
shared. What makes us differ so markedly from them is that we have largely lost
this outlook, and that we share the basically secular point of view of the
Greeks. When we say that medieval men looked on this world as a sacrament, we
mean, first, that they conceived this world to be but the visible sign of an
invisible reality. And, secondly, that they conceived this world to be a
sacrifice which they freely and gratefully dedicated to the all-good, all-true
Giver.
That
this sacramental view was a block to progress can hardly be denied. And that,
in losing it, we have rid ourselves of a liability-- ignorance, superstition,
intolerance-- seems equally obvious to many. What is not so obvious is that we
have also lost something of value. If the sacramental outlook of the Middle
Ages had issued here and there in what a modern clinician would describe as an
acute psychopathology, in others it resulted in a serenity and confidence, in a
sense of purpose, of meaningfulness, and of fulfillment, which the clinician
must admire and look for in vain, among his contemporaries."
I hope that the reader is by now
acquainted with the concluding paragraphs of my entry City Of God, and
with my concluding remarks for that entry. What remains to be repeated here is
that my main objection to Augustinianism and Thomism and the whole outlook of
the Medieval mind is its ugly disconnect from the reality of the sacramental
authority, the Church, to which they all appealed. An incredible hypocrisy took
root in the Christian mind as a result, and the emerging Renaissance struck at
the heart of that hypocrisy, with the unfortunate result of undermining the
authority of God in this world as well, and perhaps, for all time. Here is
where I see the greatest failure of Medieval European philosophy and theology,
and both St. Augustine and St. Thomas, as the foremost representatives of it,
take a large share in the blame for being too much preoccupied with matters of
comparatively little consequence, while keeping a blind eye on the greatest
problem that mattered more than all the rest of them put together.
No comments:
Post a Comment