Dèscartes and Nietzsche? But
what else could you expect from my second entry in the Cartesian series?
It would have been a horrific crime to ignore or even merely downplay what
Nietzsche says about Dèscartes, considering that what he does say is extremely
interesting and incontrovertibly pertinent to our subject at hand.
***
Another note on what I like to
call after Nietzsche the Mystical Commonwealth Of Ideas. It is so
gratifying that, considering how highly I value Dèscartes’ Discourse on
Method, as one of the greatest triumphs of human thought, my good friend Nietzsche,
despite a few occasional anti-Cartesian quibbles, has included a quotation from
this book in his Preface to the 1878 edition of Menschliches. Indeed,
Nietzsche’s odi-et-amo relationship with Dèscartes is an example of that
blessed inconsistency, of which we were talking in the preceding chapter, and
elsewhere.
Nietzsche has numerous references
to Dèscartes throughout his works, and he obviously considers him among the
very greats. In his fanciful description of the three centuries of history (seventeenth-eighteenth-nineteenth),
in the posthumous collection of his thoughts and sketches Wille zur Macht,---
as aristocratic, feministic, and animalistic,--- three philosophers are
chosen to represent each:
Dèscartes, and the rule of
reason; Rousseau, and the rule of feeling; and finally, Schopenhauer,
and the rule of craving.
In the same work, he counts him
among the greatest methodologists of history (Aristotle,
Bacon, Dèscartes, Auguste Comte). In Jenseits, he mentions him as
a bachelor, but puts him in an illustrious company of foremost philosophers:
“The
philosopher abhors marriage as a hindrance on his path to the optimum (not to
happiness, but in most cases to unhappiness). Heraclitus, Plato, Dèscartes,
Spinoza, Leibnitz, Kant, Schopenhauer,--- they were not married; one cannot
even imagine them married. A married philosopher belongs in a comedy, and Socrates,
it would seem, married ironically, just to demonstrate this proposition.”
In Ecce Homo, he praises
his exceptional honesty:
“A La
Rochefoucauld and a Dèscartes are a hundred times superior in honesty to the
foremost Germans.”
Curiously, Dèscartes being the
source of materialistic (besides idealistic) philosophy, mentioned in the last
entry, is perfectly illustrated by Nietzsche in Der Antichrist, where he
commends Dèscartes for being such a source, but criticizes him for not going
far enough:
“As
regards the lower animals, it was Dèscartes, who first had the really admirable
daring to describe them as machina; our whole physiology is directed toward
proving the truth of this doctrine. Moreover, it is illogical to set man apart,
as Dèscartes did: what we know of man today is limited precisely by the extent
to which we have regarded him, too, as a machine.”
In his earlier work Die Geburt
der Tragödie, Nietzsche instructively compares Dèscartes and Euripides:
“For
this reason (of credibility) Euripides introduced a prologue even before the
exposition, and put it into the mouth of a speaker commanding absolute trust.
Often it was a god, who had to guarantee to the public the course of the
tragedy, and so remove any possible doubt as to the reality of the myth. At the
end of his drama, Euripides required the same divine truthfulness to act as
security for the future of his protagonists. This was the function of the
ill-famed deus ex machina… Exactly as Dèscartes could only demonstrate
the reality of the empirical world by appealing to God’s veracity, his
inability to tell a lie.
Yet, despite his apparently very
high opinion of Dèscartes’ philosophical caliber, Nietzsche will not include
him among the “eight shadows” he wishes to enter the underworld to communicate
with, which is, perhaps, quite easy to explain. Nietzsche, the great
irrationalist, dislikes Cartesian rationalism (note that Aristotle is not included
among the “eight” either, apparently, for a similar reason). In Jenseits,
he famously criticizes Dèscartes the rationalist for “being superficial”:
“Plato,
more noble and innocent in such matters, wanted to prove to himself that reason
and instinct, of themselves, tend toward one goal,--- the good, God. And
since Plato, all theologians and philosophers have been on the same track: in
moral matters it has been instinct, or faith which has triumphed. Perhaps
Dèscartes ought to be excepted as the Father of Rationalism who would conceded
authority to reason alone; but reason is merely an instrument, and Dèscartes
was superficial.”
(It must be clear now why
Nietzsche prefers Plato to Aristotle [and Dèscartes]. After all, Nietzsche is
as much an idealist as Plato is! …Which may be stretching the term idealism a
little bit, but this is essentially only a matter of definition.)
In the following, every single
instance of Nietzsche’s criticism of Dèscartes is exceedingly interesting; not
that Dèscartes deserves any blame, of course, but because of a dazzling
explosion of intellectual fireworks. This is like in a spectacular chess game,
where the loser deserves no less credit (and sometimes even more) than the
winner. Here is our first example, concerning the Cartesian definition of what
is true, as raised in Nietzsche’s Wille Zur Macht (#533):
“Logical
certainty and transparency as the criteria of truth (omni illud verum est
quod clare et distincte percipitur, in Dèscartes): with that the mechanical
hypothesis concerning the world is desired and credible… But this is a crude
confusion: like simplex sigillum veri. How does one know that the real
nature of things stands in this relation to our intellect?; Could it not be
otherwise? That it is the hypothesis which gives the intellect the greatest
feeling of power and security, that is most preferred, valued, and consequently
characterized as true? The intellect posits its freest and strongest
capability and capacity as the criterion of the most valuable, consequently of
the true.”
This is not just philosophy, this
is a case of brilliant psychology, which Nietzsche is famous for, and he
obviously catches Dèscartes here in the act of basic self-flattery, which
extends to the celebrated Cartesian Cogito, ergo sum, another such
example of self-congratulatory conceit, where Dèscartes is at least perfectly
consistent in his fallacy:
…There
are still harmless self-observers who believe that there are “immediate
certainties”; for example,--- “I think,” or, as the superstition of
Schopenhauer puts it, “I will”; as though knowledge here got hold of its
object as the Ding-an-Sich, without any falsification on the part of
either the subject or the object. But that “immediate certainty,” as
well as “absolute knowledge” and the “Ding-an-Sich,” involve a contradictio
in adjecto, we really must free ourselves from the seduction of words! In
place of the immediate certainty, the philosopher finds a series of
metaphysical questions: From where do I get the concept of thinking? Why
do I believe in cause and effect? What gives me the right to speak of an
ego as cause and finally of an ego as cause of thought? (Jenseits).
And now, this magnificent tirade
made possible by Dèscartes’ ‘calling of fire upon himself,’ as
the military expression of the World War II era puts it, runs into the
following note in the Wille zur Macht collection:
There
is thinking, therefore, there is something that thinks: such is the upshot of Dèscartes’ argumentation. But that
means positing as “true a priori” our belief in the concept of substance; that
when there is thought there has to be something that thinks, is simply a
formulation of our grammatical custom of adding a doer to every deed. In short,
this is not merely the substantiation of a fact, but a logical metaphysical
postulate! Along the lines followed by Dèscartes one does not come upon
something absolutely certain, but only upon the fact of a very strong belief.
If one should reduce the proposition to “There is thinking, therefore there
are thoughts,” one has produced a mere tautology; and precisely that, which
is in question, the “reality of thought,” is not touched upon; that is,
in this form the “apparent reality” of thought cannot be denied. But
what Dèscartes desired was that thought should have, not an apparent reality,
but a reality in itself. (#484).
Such is Nietzsche’s basic
rebuttal of the Cartesian Cogito ergo sum. But should we go beyond that
to refute the whole metaphysical theory of Kant, or the whole theory of
any other great philosopher, we shall find it a surprisingly easy job. The
reason of these greats’ greatness, however, is not with their imperviousness to
a critical rout, which is never the case, but with their daring to enter, and
their graciousness in inviting us to follow them, into an enchanted
philosophical country, to which only folly and error can forge the key. It is
for this reason that while we are free, with Nietzsche, to criticize Dèscartes,
or Kant, or Schopenhauer, or anybody else at that ultimate alpine level, we
cannot help, at the same time, but to admire these targets of our criticism for
being capable of reaching so high, where we ourselves would never be able to
reach, both for the lack of oxygen up there, and for fear of being
ridiculed by posterity.
No comments:
Post a Comment