This entry’s title is taken from
Pascal’s inscription on a piece of paper, stitched into the lining of his coat,
and found after his death. This is the opening entry of the Pascal (1623-1662)
series in this section, but the reader is as always advised to look for other Pascal
references throughout the other sections of this book.
***
Pascal was one of the greatest
creative geniuses who ever lived, a brilliant mathematician, physicist, and a
prodigious inventor. He was also a great philosopher and a writer, whose
impeccable literary style, elegant expression, wit, and depth, have enormously
influenced the French language and European literature for all time. He had
accomplished several lifetimes of work of genius, by the time he died at the
age of thirty-nine, catching a deadly cold in the middle of Stockholm’s royal
winter.
He is often called a religious
philosopher, and there is some truth to that, for religion was indeed his
biggest preoccupation, especially in his later years. But it would be wrong to
see his specialized area of philosophy in theology-related matters only, as he
was much more philosophically versatile. One of his lesser known, but
exceptionally significant contributions was to the philosophy of mathematics.
In his essay De l’Esprit Géométrique, published only over a century
after his death, he looks at the issue of discovering truths, that is of
particular interest to me, considering my basic premise that truth exists only within
a specific creation, and that all creation starts with an unprovable
hypothesis.
“Pascal
argues that ideally such a method would lead to founding all propositions on
already established truths. This is, however, impossible, because these truths
require other truths to back them up; first principles therefore cannot be
reached.” (Curiously, this is a variation on the
cosmological argument for the existence of God. No wonder that, in Pascal’s
view, the human mind is powerless in attaining any kind of absolute by human
effort alone, hence his conclusion about the necessity of submission to God.
The question remains of course whether such a submission makes the human
knowledge of the absolute possible, and, to be sure, it hardly does, but,
equally sure, it does open new horizons for human endeavor by reinforcing
reason with intuition, underscoring the fact that a healthy dose of mysticism
is a sine qua non of human progress.)
“Based
on this, he argues that the procedure used in geometry is as perfect as possible,---
with certain principles assumed, and other propositions developed from them.
But there is no way to know the assumed principles to be true.
He also
uses this opportunity to develop a theory of definition. He distinguished
between definitions which are conventional labels defined by the writer, and
definitions that are within the language, and understood by everyone because
they naturally designate their referent. The second type would be
characteristic of the philosophy of essentialism. He claims that only
definitions of the first type are important to science and to mathematics,
arguing that these fields should adopt the philosophy of formalism, formulated
by Dèscartes. In De l'Art de Persuader, he looks deeper into geometry’s
axiomatic method, specifically into the question of how people come to be
convinced of the axioms upon which later conclusions are based. He agrees with
Montaigne that it is impossible to achieve certainty in these axioms and
conclusions with human methods.” (Indeed, very
few people outside the professional mathematical community ever realize that
geometry, and all mathematics, for that matter, is based on a set of unprovable
assertions. Far from being an “exact” science, mathematics is swimming in
high-grade mysticism.)
“Pascal
asserts that these principles can only be grasped through intuition (!), and that this fact underscores
the necessity for submission to God in searching out truths.” (Or, to put it in other words, one has to become a profound
mystic.)
***
But there is much more general
philosophy in his Pensées, the great book, which I had a chance to read
at a very early age. It is true that the amount of “theologicality” in
it occasionally seems overwhelming, but this is not through any fault of his.
Published posthumously as a collection of most of his unpublished thoughts and
sketches, it includes two distinctly disparate sets. One is his drafted
preparation of a theological book, under the already established title Apologie
de la Religion Chrétienne; and the other is everything else. It is for this
reason that when the Pensées was published in 1670, its full title read Pensées
de M. Pascal sur la Religion, et sur Quelques Autres Sujets.
This book, therefore, can be
seen, in part, as a magnificent collection of philosophical aphorisms of a
great subtlety and profundity. I have several favorites among them, such as
this for instance:
Tout
le malheur des hommes vient d’une seule chose, qui est de ne savoir pas
demeurer en repos dans une chambre. (#139.)
(It is true that many people are afraid of
solitude, and hate to be by themselves even for a few hours. Such an attitude
is certainly destructive, and one does not have to be a sociopath to realize
that. There needs to be time for social activity, time for one-on-one
communication with others, and, yes, time for being alone with yourself.)
Or this creepy mystical shudder: Le silence éternel de ces espaces infinis m’effraie. (#206.) (Indeed, travelling into
the outer reaches of human perception [like all great scientists do, and some
of them never return], where eternal silence reigns, is a frightening and humbling
experience. In fact, all silence is such. Remember Hamlet: “The rest is silence.”)
Curiously, there are several very
familiar quotations here, which are often attributed to their later users, an
ignominy, which needs to be rectified, as it is now in this entry: On mourra seul (#211), attributed
to Schopenhauer, or this one: Je n’ai fait celle-ci
plus longue, que parce que je n’ai pas eu le loisir de la faire plus courte (Lettres Provinciales, xvi), traditionally
attributed to Lenin, but occasionally to a number of others as well.
As a fitting conclusion to this
general entry, we shall look at Nietzsche’s peculiar attitude to Pascal, whose
intense Catholic faith he rather harshly likens, in Jenseits 46, to a “continual suicide of reason,” and then, in Morgenröte,
pronounces him a self-hater and, by the same token, a hater of
mankind. In Der Antichrist, he laments about “the corruption of Pascal, who believed that his intellect had been
destroyed by original sin, whereas it was actually destroyed by Christianity!”
(#5) And then, in Wille zur Macht, this comparison with
Schopenhauer:
Without
the Christian faith, Pascal thought, you,
no less than nature and history, will become for yourselves un monstre et un
chaos. This prophecy we have fulfilled, after the feeble optimistic
eighteenth century had prettified and rationalized man. Schopenhauer and
Pascal. In an important sense Schopenhauer is the first to take up again the
movement of Pascal: un monstre et un chaos, consequently, something to
be negated.--- History, nature, man himself. Our inability to know the truth
is the consequence of our corruption, of our moral decay; thus Pascal. And
thus, at bottom, Schopenhauer.--- The deeper the corruption of reason, the
more necessary the doctrine of salvation--- or, in Schopenhauer’s terms,
negation. (#83).
…There are many more references
to Pascal in Nietzsche, all centering on Pascal’s lamentable intellectual
martyrdom. Yet, Pascal is still one of the select eight in the already
much-quoted Nietzschean passage that must be quoted yet again, to put
Nietzsche’s opinion of Pascal in proper perspective: I too have been in the underworld to speak with a few of the dead. Four
pairs did not deny themselves to my sacrifice: Epicurus and Montaigne, Goethe
and Spinoza, Plato and Rousseau, Pascal and Schopenhauer. On these eight I fix
my eyes, and see their eyes fixed on me. May the living forgive me that
occasionally they appear to me as shades, while those men seem so alive to me.
(Vermischte Meiningen und Sprüche: #408.)
This is not just Nietzsche’s
personal opinion. This passage may well be regarded as an objective judgment of
humanity on the great Frenchman’s historical legacy.
No comments:
Post a Comment