[Beginning
with the present entry, my PreSocratica
Sempervirens sequence resumes.]
With
the pre-Socratic philosopher, poet, social commentator, and religious critic Xenophanes
of Colophon (570 BC-480 BC) we are returning to the proper chronological
order, disrupted by our detour into latter-day Pythagoreanism of Philolaus and
Archytas (see my entries on them posted on December 18th – 19th,
2013.)
Xenophanes
is often considered as the founder of the Eleatic school of philosophical
thinking, whose most famous alumnus was Parmenides, who is himself often
described as the school’s founder. We are however better off treating him
separately from the Eleatics, both on his own merit and to avoid the
controversy as to whether he was an Eleatic or not, which is totally unnecessary.
(Let the aspiring scholars debate this PhD fodder…)
Xenophanes
is most renowned for having explicitly rejected Greek polytheism and anthropomorphism,
and his development of the concept of One God, who is abstract, universal,
unchanging, immobile, and forever present. For this reason, he is often seen as
the first explicit monotheist in Western philosophy of religion. I am, however,
convinced, as I have asserted throughout all relevant sections of this work,
that monotheism has been the religion of the Greek philosophers from the
very start, which ought not to diminish, of course, his, Xenophanes’s, personal
accomplishments as a champion of explicit
monotheism.
Modern
historiography of philosophy points out a curious fact, namely, that until the
1950’s, there existed some controversy over many aspects of the Xenophanes
phenomenon, including whether or not he could be properly characterized as a
philosopher. In today’s philosophical and classics discourse, it is asserted
that he is recognized as one of the most important pre-Socratic philosophers.
This is an interesting claim, and I am going to investigate it further at a
later date, but so far it is true that among my glorified staple sources of
philosophical historiography, Nietzsche and Russell, Xenophanes, although
favorably mentioned, does not occupy a place among the greatest. As the reader
may have noticed, Nietzsche does not include him in his wonderfully
idealized company of the early Greek masters Thales, Anaximander, Heraclitus,
Parmenides, Anaxagoras, Empedocles, Democritus, and Socrates. Bertrand
Russell does not give him a separate chapter either, mentioning Xenophanes in
his big chapter on Heraclitus. But this mention is in itself worth taking a
look at, and here it is, slightly contracted for the purpose of brevity:
“Between Pythagoras and Heraclitus
there was a philosopher of less importance, namely Xenophanes. His date is
uncertain, mainly determined by the fact that he alludes to Pythagoras, while
Heraclitus alludes to him. He believed all things to be made of earth and
water. He believed in one God, unlike men in thought and form, who “without
toil swayeth all things by the force of his mind.” He made fun of the
Pythagorean doctrine of transmigration, and believed it impossible to ascertain
the truth in matters of theology (which is exactly my point, as expressed in my aphorism “if
theological proof were available, who would then need the faith?!”). Xenophanes has his place in the
succession of rationalists who were opposed to the mystical tendencies of
Pythagoras and others, but as an independent thinker he is not of the first rank.”
This
rather unflattering characterization, given to Xenophanes by Russell, needs
further investigation in the light of the more recent claim concerning
Xenophanes’ preeminent greatness, which will be done at a later date, as I have
promised. In the meantime, let us next examine what Nietzsche has to say about
Xenophanes in his Philosophy During the Tragic Age of the Greeks, which
examination will certainly require a separate entry. As we are going to find
out in tomorrow’s entry, Nietzsche and Russell sharply differ on the question
of Xenophanes’ rationalism versus mysticism. Who is right?..
No comments:
Post a Comment