Sunday, April 6, 2014

KNOWLEDGE VERSUS PERCEPTION IN PLATO


As Lenin famously pronounced in this pseudo-philosophical statement, “matter is objective reality which is given to us in perception.” Our friend Bertrand Russell, too, reasonably starts his analysis of Plato’s theory of knowledge and perception, with the reminder that normal people have usually taken it for granted that all knowledge comes to us through the experience of our senses, that is perception. Curiously enough the same premise opens Plato’s Dialogue Theaetetus, but not to reiterate what could easily be mistaken for a truism, but rather to set up a punching bag, which the rest of the Dialogue proceeds to cut up to shreds. Here is that opening setup:

Socrates: Once more, Theaetetus, what is knowledge? and do not say that you cannot tell; but quit yourself like a man, and by the help of God you will be able to tell.

Theaetetus: After this, Socrates, I should be ashamed not to try my best. He who knows, perceives what he knows, and, as far as I can see, knowledge is perception.

To which Socrates reacts:

Socrates: Well, you have delivered yourself of a very important doctrine about knowledge; it is indeed the opinion of Protagoras, who has another way of expressing it. Man, he says, is the measure of all things, of the existence of things that are, and of the non-existence of things that are not… Then, doesn’t he say that things are to you such as they appear to you, and to me such as they appear to me? Then, perception always is of existence, and being the same as knowledge is unerring?

Anybody who is familiar with Plato’s Socrates realizes at this point that what Socrates is driving at, is that perception cannot be knowledge. Through a rather lengthy series of arguments, Plato’s Socrates is, indeed, coming to his final point concerning the inadequacy of perception as knowledge. We perceive through our eyes and ears and not with them. Some of our knowledge is not connected with any sense organ at all. The mind contemplates some things through its own instrumentality, others through the bodily faculties. Only the mind can reach existence, and we can’t reach truth, if we don’t reach existence. It follows that we can’t know things through the senses alone, since through the senses alone we can’t know that things exist. Ergo, knowledge consists in reflection, and not in impressions, and perception is not knowledge because it has no part in apprehending truth, since it has none in apprehending existence.(The teal font here belongs to Russell quotes.)

Now, rather than going into the details of the Theaetetus, I recommend to the reader to read this Dialogue if these details are of interest to him, or her. On my part I would like to add a few comments on Plato’s use of mathematics and linguistics in this context. Here again is Bertrand Russell, whose thoughts on Plato’s math I am quoting here to establish a point of reference for further exploration at a later date.

I come now to understanding of numbers. There are two very different things to consider here: on the one hand, the propositions of arithmetic (2+2=4), and, on the other, empirical propositions of enumeration (“I have ten fingers”).

I should agree with Plato that arithmetic, and pure mathematics generally, is not derived from perception. Pure mathematics consists of tautologies, analogous to “men are men,” but usually more complicated. To know that a mathematical proposition is correct, we do not have to study the world, but only the meanings of the symbols; and the symbols are found to be such words as “or” and “not” and “all” and “some,” which do not, like “Socrates,” denote anything in the actual world. Mathematical truth is, indeed, independent of perception; but it is truth of a very peculiar sort, and is concerned only with symbols.

Propositions of enumerations are in a different category, and are, at least in part, dependent on perception. Thus, in the statement “I have ten fingers” perception clearly plays a smaller part, and conception, a larger part, than in the statement “this is red.” The matter, however, is only one of degree.

These considerations show that, while there is a formal kind of knowledge, such as logic and mathematics, which is not derived from perception, Plato’s arguments regarding all other knowledge are fallacious.

And finally, in his involvement of linguistics, which is particularly familiar to me, as a professional, in all its aspects, Plato apparently gets lost in the intricacies of the science of language sorely undeveloped in his day and even much later. In the following classic passage, known as the Socrates Dream, an atomistic generalization of language is promoted, comparing letters to elementary particles [atoms], and their complex combinations to [molecules]. (This is obviously my shorthand word here. Socrates never uses it). After this discussion, it should become clear why the philosophical discourse in the Theaetetus will remain admittedly inconclusive.

Socrates: I too had a dream, and heard in my dream that the primeval letters, or elements, out of which you and I and all other things are compounded, have no reason or explanation: you can only name them, but no predicate can be either affirmed or denied of them, for in the one case existence, in the other non-existence is already implied, neither of which must be added, if you speak of this or that thing by itself. It should not be called itself, or that, or each, or alone, or this, or the like, for these go about everywhere, and are applied to all things, but are distinct from them; but if the first elements could be described, and had a definition of their own, they would be spoken of apart from all else. But none of these primeval elements can be defined, but they can only be named, for they have nothing but a name, and the things compounded of them, as they are complex, are expressed by a combination of names, for the combination of names is the essence of any definition. Thus, the elements or letters are only objects of perception and cannot be defined or known; but the syllables or combinations of them are known, and expressed, and apprehended by true opinion. When, thus, anyone forms the true opinion of anything without a rational explanation, you can say that his mind is exercised, but has no knowledge, for he who cannot give and receive a reason for a thing has no knowledge of that thing; but when he adds rational explanation, then he is perfected in knowledge.

In semantics, Plato’s confusion arises from a lack of proper understanding of how words acquire their original meanings, and how these meanings never remain fixed, but undergo gradual changes, which, however, are not to be ignored or exaggerated, and even less ridiculed. To be sure, the formal language of mathematics answers to different laws than any living language, and attempts to create artificial languages designed for international communication have famously failed. My general understanding of Plato’s linguistic failure is that he wished to treat the living language just like certain linguistic engineers more than two millennia later wished to see the artificial product of their engineering, but unlike Plato, they understood that none of the existing languages was fit for that function.

…Just as I was about to say au revoir to the Plato subsection, the idea for an offshoot for this last entry has come to me, with the natural title Plato’s Problem, referring to the gap between knowledge and experience, described and so named by none other than our friend Noam Chomsky. And so, welcome now to what has received the name Plato’s Problem, courtesy of Ecce Chomsky. (My very long entry devoted to Chomsky and boasting of this fancy title Ecce Chomsky will be posted (necessarily, in terms of chronological continuity) much later, after I am done with all earlier giants of Western philosophical thought.)

No comments:

Post a Comment