Taking
the cue from Nietzsche’s description of Plato as the first hybrid type in
the history of philosophy, we approach his towering figure with some
trepidation, as there is so much to say about him, and yet, we have deprived
him and his offshoot Aristotle of a special section, which could easily be
filled to capacity. In that case, however, this work would surely have been
transformed into a history of philosophy, which has been the last thing on my
mind, and the particular place allotted to Plato and Aristotle on these pages
is determined rather by my personal inclination to talk on this or that specific
subject than to present a picture of the whole.
Yet,
a sort of preamble to the great Greek is, probably, in order, and I am offering
it here, starting with this remarkable brief summary of Plato by Bertrand
Russell:
Plato and Aristotle were the most influential of all philosophers,
ancient, medieval, or modern; and of the two it was Plato who had the greater
effect upon subsequent ages. I say it for these two reasons: first, that
Aristotle himself is an outcome of Plato; second, that Christian theology and
philosophy, at any rate, until the thirteenth century, was much more Platonic
than Aristotelian. It is necessary, therefore, in a history of philosophic thought,
to treat Plato, and to a lesser degree Aristotle, more fully than we treat any
of their predecessors or successors.
The most important matters in Plato’s philosophy are: first, his
Utopia, which was the earliest of a lengthy series; second, his theory of
ideas, which was a pioneer attempt to deal with the still unsolved problem of
the universals; third, his arguments in favor of immortality; fourth, his cosmogony;
fifth his conception of knowledge as reminiscence, rather than perception.
From
this enumeration alone, it comes clear that Plato was the first philosopher who
laid the foundations of professional philosophy, as we know it. But there was a
price for his greatness. In Nietzsche’s words, Plato was no longer a “pure
type,” but the first “hybrid type,” and although Russell does not
resort to Nietzsche’s characterization, he spells it out in the following
passage, reminiscent of Marcus Aurelius’ opening credits in his Thoughts:
The purely philosophical influences on Plato were Pythagoras, Parmenides,
Heraclitus, and Socrates.
From Pythagoras, Plato derived the Orphic elements in his
philosophy: the religious trend, the belief in immortality, the
other-worldliness, the priestly tone, and all that is involved in the simile of
the cave; also his respect for mathematics, and his intimate intermingling of
intellect and mysticism.
From Parmenides, he derived the belief that reality is eternal and
timeless, and that on logical grounds all change must be illusory.
From Heraclitus, he derived the negative doctrine that there is
nothing permanent in the sensible world. This, combined with the doctrine of
Parmenides, led to the conclusion that knowledge is not to be derived from the
senses, but is only to be achieved by the intellect. This, in turn, fitted well
with Pythagoreanism.
From Socrates, he learned his preoccupation with ethical problems,
and his tendency to seek teleological, rather than mechanical, explanations of
the world. “The Good” dominated his thought more than that of the
pre-Socratics, and it is difficult not to attribute this fact to the influence
of Socrates.
There
are therefore five lines of philosophical inquiry which Plato pursued that we
need to comment on in a very general form in this entry.
Plato’s
‘Utopia’ has already been discussed at some length in my entry Plato’s
Totalitarian Politeia in the Collective section, and there is no
need to provide an additional entry on it in this section. Of some interest,
however, is Russell’s explanation for the sources of Plato’s totalitarian
mentality, and I would like to quote it here, with a simultaneous memo to
myself that Russell’s argumentation may be a useful addition to my original
entry, when I undertake its revision and the accompanying expansion, in my next
stage of work.
Plato was a well-to-do aristocrat, Russell writes, related to various people who
were concerned in the rule of Thirty Tyrants. He was a young man when Athens
was defeated (in the Peloponnesian War), and could attribute the defeat to
democracy, which his social position and his family connections made him
despise. He was a pupil of Socrates, for whom he had a profound affection and
respect, and who was put to death by a democracy. It is not, therefore,
surprising that he should turn to Sparta for an adumbration of his ideal
commonwealth.
In
other (Shakespeare’s) words, tired with all this (democracy), for restful
(totalitarianism) Plato cried. It is thus important to put such things as,
for instance, totalitarianism, getting back to it after a long pause, in their
proper context, and see and appreciate them not as a social ideal for all time,
but as a natural and reasonable alternative to a democracy running amok.
The
next component of Platonism, following Russell’s lead, is Plato’s Theory of
Ideas which also includes his notion of The Good. It is perhaps the
most complex and comprehensive subject in all Platonism, with a wide range of
implications. I will discuss it accordingly at some length in my entry Plato
And Christianity and its specific “being versus becoming” subcomponent
in the entry after that, titled To Be Or To Become.
For
the third component of Platonism see my entry Apostle Paul As A Philosopher,
where Plato’s theory of immortality will be discussed in the context
of major philosophical influences on Apostle Paul’s thinking.
Russell’s
fourth component of Platonism is Plato’s ontology, called cosmogony by
Russell. My preference for the word ontology can be explained by the
title of my Platonic entry, devoted to it: Plato’s Cosmology And
Pre-Socratic Ontology, which follows To Be Or To Become.
And
finally, the fifth component of Platonism is discussed in my last entry in the
Platonic sequence of this section, under the title Knowledge Versus
Perception In Plato which, though, does not round up the Platonic subsection in the Magnificent
Shadows, nor my numerous further discussions, and passing references to
Plato, which will keep popping up here and there along the rest of the way.
No comments:
Post a Comment