Wednesday, April 30, 2014

METAPHYSICS AT CONCEPTION. PART III.


Part III.

How far, then, does Aristotle depart from Plato’s idealistic duality, which he himself criticizes? Apparently, not far at all. If the human soul is a form, not only is this form superior to the matter and spatial boundary of the body, but it can exist independently from the body, and eternally as well… At least, this is what every Christian reader of Aristotle has believed, according to the doctrine of his Church, and, not surprisingly, has found in Aristotle’s theory of forms too! Here is what Bertrand Russell writes about Aristotle’s clandestine Platonism:

The view that forms are substances which exist independently of the matter in which they are exemplified, seems to expose Aristotle to his own arguments against Platonic Ideas. Forms are intended to be different from universals, but they have many of the same characteristics. Form is, allegedly, more real than matter; this is reminiscent of the sole reality of the ideas. The change that Aristotle makes in Plato’s metaphysics is less than he represents it as being.

And here’s a paragraph on this subject by the eminent German classical scholar, philosopher, and theologian Eduard Zeller (1814-1908), taken from his Platonische Studien (1939), as appropriately quoted by Russell:

The final explanation of Aristotle’s want of clearness on this subject is however to be found in the fact that he had only half emancipated himself from Plato’s tendency to hypostatize ideas. The Forms had for him, as the Ideas had for Plato, a metaphysical existence of their own as conditioning individual things. And keenly as he followed the growth of ideas out of experience, it is still true that these ideas, especially at the point where they are farthest removed from experience and immediate perception, are metamorphosed in the end from a logical product of human thought into an immediate presentment of a supersensible world, and the object, in that sense, of an intellectual intuition.

This whole discussion is by no means to imply that Aristotle was overrated as an original thinker, and that he was just another, most talented, but still a follower of Plato. Aristotle’s originality and uniqueness have been proven by the totality of his titanic philosophical endeavor, and his “clandestine Platonism,” as I call it, occupies just this limited aspect of his metaphysics, where the influence of Plato is, indeed, overwhelming.

We could go on and on with our discussion of Aristotle’s theory of forms, but the reader can satisfy his or her interest by going to the source, Aristotle’s Metaphysics, or reading about his metaphysics in reputable histories of philosophy. There are a few brief points left for me to make, before I move to my next subject. The form of a thing is both its essence and its primary substance. Forms are substantial, but universals are not. Not every thing contains matter; there are eternal things devoid of matter. And, lastly, things increase in “actuality” by acquiring and developing form, but matter without form is only a “potentiality.” This last distinction needs some clarification.

The doctrine of matter and form distinguishes between potentiality and actuality. Bare matter is conceived as a potentiality of form; all change consists in an accrual of form: after the change, the thing has more of form than before. What has more form is said to be more actual. God is pure form and pure actuality. And it is to the question of God, as perceived by Aristotle, that we turn our attention in the next entry.

No comments:

Post a Comment