(Also
see my related entries Art As Being
Rather Than Becoming, posted on February 13th, 2013, and Being And Becoming, posted on February 2nd,
2014.)
The
philosophical problem of Being and Becoming brings us back again
to the monumental question, first posed by Anaximander, differently, and
mutually contradictorily, answered by Parmenides and Heraclitus, and then that
contradiction attempted to be overcome by the Atomists and Plato. Democritus’
solution was logically, physically and structuralistically superb: a
host of Parmenidean permanent ones was engaged in a Heraclitean flux,
therefore, the permanence was inside of the indivisible, whereas
the change was outside it, in the shifting relationships of the basic
structural units, the atoms. Everything was splendid about such an explanation,
except just one thing: being cruelly mechanistic and non-teleological, it
denied edification to human morality, and made the very purpose of
learning and knowledge as such, non-teleological, in other words, purposeless.
That is if we had a good purpose in mind, understanding that its
only alternative, bad purpose, was unthinkable and unacceptable. (For,
the concept of “Jenseits von Gut und Böse” had not been invented
yet, in Plato’s time!) Having introduced the concept of The Good as the
highest form of existence, and teleology as a concomitant of morality, Plato
had to come up with something quite different, infinitely more complex and
complicated than atomism, since by going teleological, he introduced an
additional and highly convoluted factor into the equation, which from now on
would have to be accounted for in virtually any philosophical contemplation.
Here
is a key passage from Plato’s Dialogue Timaeus, where Timaeus says this
(27d5-28b2):
“First, I must distinguish between that which always is, and
never becomes, and which is apprehended by reason and reflection; and that
which always becomes and never is, and is conceived by opinion with the help of
sense. All that becomes and is created is the work of a cause, and fair is what
the craftsman makes after an eternal pattern, but whatever is fashioned after a
created pattern is not fair.”
We
shall return to the much-important Dialogue Timaeus, and to the larger
context of this brief passage, in our remaining Platonic entries, but so far
let us recapitulate the essence of Being and Becoming.
The
problem of being and becoming is the problem of permanence and
change where being is equivalent to permanence and becoming
is equivalent to change. Then how do we get from a permanent single form to
all those ever-changing and multiple particulars? To Plato the answer appears
simple: one thing can have many reflections. But those reflections are only
illusions of the real thing whereas all commonsense particulars are real to us,
while their Platonic form, or idea, although by no means an illusion, is at
least a generalization, or abstraction, once again, from the commonsense point
of view and it is impossible to imagine
an abstraction in reality. Given a choice between a down-to-earth triangle,
roughly traced in the sand, and its ghostly ideal counterpart,
corresponding to every demand imposed on it by mathematics, it is hard to agree
that a perfect abstraction can be real, and our figure in the sand can not,
although the incoming wave makes the last point moot.
It
is much easier to imagine our immortal soul as being, in the sense of permanence,
and our physical body as becoming, in the sense of change, such
as growing up, then growing old, coming into being, as we say, perhaps,
inaccurately, from the standpoint of Platonic philosophy, but quite
understandably, from the point of common sense, and then passing away,
or ceasing to be, as we may say. As it turns out, common sense and
philosophy clash in all these considerations to the point of providing
basically antipodal definitions, as applied to the concepts of being and
becoming. Philosophers are trying to convince us that we are talking
about apples and oranges here, that philosophy is deep and refined, whereas our
common sense is shallow and crude. But this is exactly how philosophy as such
gets a bad name! In order to restore a good doxa to her, she must be
reconciled to the common sense, and this is really not too much to ask, is it?!
In
the passage from the Timaeus above there is an extremely curious phrase
which must not pass unnoticed: “All that becomes
and is created is the work of a cause…”
It
is only everything becoming (that is, belonging to the illusory world of
the senses), which belongs to the causality chain as an effect and then the
cause of the next effect, etc. Being is uncreated, that is, uncaused.
There is therefore no causality in Plato’s reality. (The role of being as
the starting first cause is rather vague and the logic behind the eternal and
permanent, suddenly becoming creative, is elusive, and probably not at all
clear to Plato himself.) It is therefore logical to exclude all traces of
causality, even the first cause, from the realm of Being. (We shall
discuss it in greater detail in the entry on Plato’s Cosmogony.)
The
question of Plato’s causality is interestingly picked up by George Long, in the
following passage from his Introduction to the Thoughts of Marcus
Aurelius: “…When Plato says, ‘Nothing ever is,
but is always becoming,’ he destroys by this not all practical, but all
speculative notions of cause and effect. The whole series of things as they
appear to us, must be contemplated in time, that is, in succession, and we
conceive or suppose intervals between one state of things and another state of
things, so that there is a priority and sequence, and interval, and Being, and
a ceasing to be, and beginning and ending. But there is nothing of the kind in the
Nature of Things. It is an everlasting continuity.”
There
are two big points here: Is Plato’s dictum such a blow to causality as it
seems, at least to Dr. Long? Why should the continuity of becoming be free from
causality? Isn’t this a matter of interpretation, rather than of fact? To the
contrary of what Long says, even Hegel’s dialectics is a continuum of becoming.
How else would a synthesis occur except by the thesis becoming this
something else through the inbreeding act of copulation with its closest living
relative, the antithesis?
And
the other one, only slightly related to it, does the concept of time involve a
discreteness similar to the quantum theory? In this case, it is indeed
impossible to see time as anything but succession, and the notion of an
everlasting continuity becomes the conceptual bridge between time and
timelessness. In such a case, Plato’s nothing ever is, may be
interpreted as a blow against the discreetness of time, in the sense that ‘is’
allows us to relate to ‘was’ and ‘will be,’ but not in the
sense of the Biblical name I AM for God, which, on the contrary,
eliminates the past and the future from the equation, making the present time
non-historical, and representative of timelessness.
By
the same token, Plato’s “always becoming” is taken out from the discreetness of time, but still
remains ambiguous, which puts it smack back into the center of gravity of that
imponderable magic bridge floating in-between time and timelessness.
No comments:
Post a Comment